Displaying: 81-100 of 278 documents

0.159 sec

81. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 3/4
Adina Bozga The world given as pre-given: a phenomenological approach to world-constitution
82. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 3/4
Book Reviews
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Dan ZAHAVI, Husserl and Transcendental Intersubjectivity. A Response to the Linguistic-Pragmatic Critique (Adina Bozga); Françoise DASTUR, Chair et langage. Essais sur Merleau-Ponty (Delia Popa); Jean GREISCH (éd.), Michel Henry et l’épreuve de la vie (Mihail Neamţu); Elisabeth STRÖKER, The Husserlian Foundations of Science (Adina Bozga); John McCUMBER, Metaphysics and Oppression, Heidegger’s Challenge to Western Philosophy (Daniela Pălăşan); Marc RICHIR, Phénoménologie en esquisses. Nouvelles fondations (Horaţiu Crişan); Raphaël GÉLY, La genèse du sentir. Essai sur Merleau-Ponty (Ligia Beltechi); John SALLIS, Force of Imagination: The Sense of the Elemental (Roxana Albu); Bin KIMURA, L’entre. Une approche phénoménologique de la schizophrénie (Ciprian Ţiprigan); Dermot MORAN, Tim MOONEY (eds.), The Phenomenology Reader (Radu M. Oancea); Ion COPOERU, Structuri ale constituirii (Dorel Bucur); Fabio CIARAMELLI, La distruzione del’desiderio. Il narcisismo nell’epoca di consumo di massa (Anca Dumitru); Pierre KELLER, Husserl and Heidegger on Human Experience (Ciprian Mîinea)
83. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Daniele de Santis, Orcid-ID Claudio Majolino Phaenomenologia sub specie Platonis: Editors’ Introduction
84. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Emiliano Trizio Husserl’s Timaeus. Plato’s Creation Myth and the Phenomenological Concept of Metaphysics as the Teleological Science of the World
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to Husserl, Plato played a fundamental role in the development of the notion of teleology, so much so that Husserl viewed the myth narrated in the Timaeus as a fundamental stage in the long history that he hoped would eventually lead to a teleological science of the world grounded in transcendental phenomenology. This article explores this interpretation of Plato’s legacy in light of Husserl’s thesis that Plato was the initiator of the ideal of genuine science. It also outlines how Husserl sought conceptual resources within transcendental phenomenology to turn the key elements of Plato’s creation myth into rigorous scientific ideas.
85. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Aurélien Djian Orcid-ID Hen epi pollon. The Origin of Husserl’s Eidetic Variation and the Divide Between Plato and Aristotle on the Universal
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is commonly known that Husserl’s eidetic variation is of paramount importance for phenomenology. For if phenomenology is a science of pure essences and formulates scientific laws about such essences, there has to be something like a method to follow in order to discover and test such eidetic truths; and this method is dubbed as eidetic variation. Now, a crucial aspect of this method has not been under active consideration yet: namely, as Husserl stresses in Experience and Judgment, that the eidetic variation is somehow to be related to the Greek notion of “hen epi pollôn”: the one over the many. An expression first used by Aristotle in the context of his dispute with Plato on the status of intelligible objects as universals. Accordingly, it seems clear that, by using this expression, Husserl wanted to refer his method to this Aristotle/Plato divide. The aim of this paper is to take this claim seriously, and to show, by an historical detour which takes into consideration this dispute, in which sense this method can be considered as a crucial contribution to the tradition to which phenomenology belongs, namely the Platonic-Aristotelian tradition.
86. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
William H. Koch Phenomenology and the Problem of Universals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper argues that the Problem of Universals as derived from Plato, i.e. the question of how abstract universal knowledge is possible and what that knowledge is of, is at the center of Phenomenology. It will be shown how Husserl’s answer to this question, via phenomenological epoche and eidetic variation, orients him primarily within the field of modern philosophy and is open to the standard criticisms of universal knowledge and abstraction offered by Hume and Berkeley. Heidegger, in more overtly recognizing the origin of the problem in Plato and orienting phenomenology directly in relation to the Platonic answer to that problem, is able to achieve a clarity about the modern prejudices of philosophy and so is able to reinvent phenomenology free from the distortions of an unquestioned metaphysics of presence and assumption of the necessity of structure grounded in an unrecognized substance ontology.
87. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Katherine Davies Heidegger’s Reading(s) of the Phaedrus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In the 1920s and 30s, Heidegger developed three explicit readings of Plato’s Phaedrus. These readings emphasize different dimensions of Plato’s dialogue and, at times, seem even to contradict one another. Though Heidegger pursues quite different interpretations of the dialogue, he remains steadfast in praising this Platonic dialogue above all others. I argue that these explicit readings provide fertile ground for reconsidering Heidegger’s engagement with Plato and not just with Platonism. I further develop an argument that a fourth, implicit reading of Phaedrus can be found in Heidegger’s own dialogical text from the late 1940s, “das abendländische Gespräch”. I suggest that it is in this conversational text, where Plato’s name is never once mentioned, that Heidegger manages his most authentic engagement with the Platonic dialogue and with Plato himself.
88. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Georgios Tsagdis, Rozemund Uljée Orcid-ID Subject to Soul, Object to World: Jan Patočka’s Platonism of Care
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Jan Patočka thought travels on the parallel rails of a-subjective phenomenology and the care of the soul. For the most part, their parallel supportive function remains unproblematic. However, in order to appreciate the significance of Patočka’s contribution to the history of philosophy and the stakes of its undertaking, the alignment of the rails must be tested: how can a phenomenology, which strives to dislocate the subject from its experiential privilege, attempt to bring the soul into both the onto-epistemic as well as the ethico-political epicentre? By revising Platonism, Patočka wagers an ambitious, fragile answer, which opens nothing less than the space of freedom.
89. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Sylvain Roux Is Levinas a Platonist?: The Interpretation of Plato in Totality and Infinity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Levinas’ relationship to Platonism is ambiguous. In Totality and Infinity, indeed, references to Plato’s writings are multiple and Levinas depicts Plato as following two diverging paths. On the one hand, Levinas considers Plato’s writings to be works that consecrate the primacy of identity over difference, of the Same over the Other. On the other hand, Platonism is presented as a philosophy of absolute transcendence due to its refusal to make the Good a simple ontological principle and to its attempt to free the Good from all forms of totality. The present study aims to show that, although Levinas criticizes the first path taken by Plato, he conceives of himself as partially in line with Plato’s philosophy of absolute transcendence, albeit in a paradoxical form. In this way, Levinas understands the meaning of the Platonic approach in an original way.
90. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Paul Slama The Onto-Agathological Fold of Metaphysics: Aristotle, Plato and Heidegger
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The goal of this paper is twofold. First, it aims to identify in Heidegger’s work a determination of the history of metaphysics parallel to the famous onto-theological one, and which I will label onto-agathological. Based upon a text from the course of 1935, “Einführung in die Metaphysik,” I argue that for Heidegger the history of metaphysics is not only the Aristotelian onto-theology, but is also characterized by the Platonic pre-eminence of the good over being (Republic 509c). In short, it is an onto-agathological history. Second, and as a consequence of the first point, I will flesh out the hypothesis of another history metaphysics, and emphasize its strong phenomenological content which stands in opposition to the Neo-Kantianism of Windelband and Rickert.
91. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Bernhard Waldenfels Responsivity and Co-Responsivity from a Phenomenological Point of View
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article I shall largely make use of terms like “responding,” “responsive,” and “responsivity.” These terms are not part of traditional philosophy. They became indispensable for my own thinking when I tried to develop a theory of radical Fremdheit, of alienness or otherness. Hence I came to a sort of responsive phenomenology that does not replace current variants of phenomenology, but sets a new tone. This is what I try to show in my article. I shall proceed in four steps. In the first step, dealing with the formation of the theory, I try to show how our experience of radical otherness leads to the key concept of responsivity (sect. 1–3). In the second step, I shall describe the main features of responsivity and its pathological deviations (sect. 4–6). In the third step, this perspective will be expanded by referring to co-affection and co-responsivity as elements of proto-sociality (sect. 7). The fourth and last step will offer a practical outlook, raising the question to what extent responsivity can be organised and institutionalised (sect. 8).
92. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
J. Leavitt Pearl À Denys: Tracing Jean-Luc Marion’s Dionysian Hermeneutics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Since his 1977 The Idol and Distance (L’idole et la distance), Jean-Luc Marion has almost continually drawn upon the work of the 5th-6th century Christian mystic Pseudo-Denys the Areopagite (Pseudo-Dionysius), not only within his explicitly theological considerations, but throughout his Cartesian and phenomenological work as well. The present essay maps out the influence of Denys upon Marion’s thinking, organizing Marion’s career into a three-part periodization, each of which corresponds to a distinct portion of the Dionysian corpus—in Marion’s work of the seventies the Celestial Hierarchy and the Ecclesiastical Hierarchy are foregrounded, in the eighties this emphasis is shifted to the The Divine Names, and in the nineties The Mystical Theology takes center stage. Insofar as these emphases directly correlate to the unique tasks that Marion has set himself in each of these various periods, Dionysius is revealed as a hermeneutical key, unlocking and clarifying crucial aspects of Marion’s theologically-inflected phenomenology.
93. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Thomas Byrne A “Principally Unacceptable” Theory: Husserl’s Rejection and Revision of His Philosophy of Meaning Intentions from the Logical Investigations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper accomplishes two goals. First, the essay elucidates Husserl’s descriptions of meaning consciousness from the 1901 Logical Investigations. I examine Husserl’s observations about the three ways we can experience meaning and I discuss his conclusions about the structure of meaning intentions. Second, the paper explores how Husserl reworked that 1901 theory in his 1913/14 Revisions to the Sixth Investigation. I explore how Husserl transformed his descriptions of the three intentions involved in meaningful experience. By doing so, Husserl not only recognized intersubjective communication as the condition of possibility of linguistic meaning acts, but also transformed his account of the structure of both signitive and intuitive acts. In the conclusion, I cash out this analysis, by showing how, on the basis of these new insights, Husserl reconstructs his theory of fulfillment.
94. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Alexandru Bejinariu Vincent Blok, Heidegger’s Concept of Philosophical Method: Innovating Philosophy in the Age of Global Warming (Routledge, 2019)
95. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Nicola Spano Andrea Staiti, Etica Naturalistica e Fenomenologia (il Mulino, 2020)
96. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Valeria Bizzari Michela Beatrice Ferri (ed.), The Reception of Husserlian Phenomenology in North America (Springer, 2019)
97. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 21
Paul Marinescu, Orcid-ID Cristian Ciocan Orcid-ID Introduction: From Witnessing to Testimony
98. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 21
Gert-Jan van der Heiden Testimony and Engagement: On the Four Elements of Witnessing
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In order to develop a hermeneutic-phenomenological analysis of testimony, this essay will first argue that testimony is “said in many ways” without being homonymous and that contemporary epistemological approaches to testimony are not capable of accounting for all paradigmatic forms of testimony. Second, it is argued, following and extending the work of Paul Ricoeur, that by emphasizing the sense of engagement or Bezogenheit as a basic characteristic of testimony, we may find another approach to testimony that offers a phenomenological alternative to the observational model of witnessing and the accompanying conception of testimony as report. Third, this approach is further developed and analyzed in terms of the four elements of testimony, namely, subject matter, witness, act of testifying, and addressee.
99. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 21
Michele Averchi Knowledge by Hearing: A Husserlian Antireductionist Phenomenology of Testimony
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, I argue that Husserl offers an important, although almost completely neglected so far, contribution to the reductionist/antireductionist debate about testimony. Through a phenomenological analysis, Husserl shows that testimony works through the constitution of an intentional intersubjective bond between the speaker and the hearer. In this paper I focus on the Logical Investigations, a 1914 manuscript now published as text 2 in Husserliana 20.2, and a 1931 manuscript now published as Appendix 12 in Husserliana 15. I argue that, in those texts, Husserl highlights three essential phenomenological features of testimony: a) testimony is personal, meaning that it only takes place among persons, b) testimony is social, meaning that it requires the joint effort of multiple cognitive agents, c) testimony is community-building, meaning that it generates a long-lasting social bond among the parts involved.
100. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 21
Rafael Pérez Baquero Orcid-ID Witnessing Catastrophe: Testimony and Historical Representation Within and Beyond the Holocaust
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper explores the contemporary phenomenological and psychoanalytical analyses of testimonies regarding traumatic historical events, with special attention to how such testimonies pose new challenges for the historiography of historical events in which witnesses participated. By exploring discussions on the memory of the Holocaust as well as the Spanish Civil War and Francoist repression, this paper addresses the extent to which the tensions and temporalities underlying the process of bearing witness to and giving testimony about traumatic historical events might reshape how their history is being told, written, and remembered.