Displaying: 61-80 of 275 documents

0.18 sec

61. Philo: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Paul Pistone Introduction
62. Philo: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Peter van Inwagen Some Remarks on the Modal Ontological Argument
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines the so-called modal ontological argument. It pays special attention to the role that the symmetry and transitivity of the accessibility relation play in the argument, and examines various approaches to a defense of the “possibility premise,” the premise of the argument that states that the existence of a perfect being is metaphysically possible. It contains an analysis of Gödel’s attempt to show that this premise is true, and of a recent formulation by David Johnson of Gödel’s argument.
63. Philo: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
William Wainwright Two (or Maybe One and a Half) Cheers for Perfect Being Theology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In a series of influential articles published in the 1980s, Thomas Morris argued that the most promising approach to many issues in the philosophy of religion is “perfect being theology.” A philosopher who adopts it begins by construing God as a maximally perfect being and then fills the conception in by using his or her modal intuitions and intuitions concerning what properties are and are not perfections. While I am sympathetic with Morris’s program, two aspects seem problematic. More justification is needed for construing God as a maximally perfect being, and the appeal to intuitions needs more support than Morris provides for it. I will comment on both difficulties.
64. Philo: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Peter Byrne Is Morality Undercut by Evolutionary Naturalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper surveys the argument that a secular world-view that is committed to a neo-Darwinian account of human origins generates a vicious form of moral skepticism. The argument turns around the claim that Darwinism entails the unreliability of moral sense or conscience. This argument is analyzed and found wanting. It rests on a major error about the scope of evolutionary biology in explaining human thought.
65. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Eric Reitan Moving the Goalposts? The Challenge of Philosophical Engagement with the Public God Debates
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
When philosophers contribute to public debates as polarized as contemporary ones about theistic belief, it is common to encounter responses that, philosophically, are woefully misguided. While it is tempting to simply dismiss them, a closer examination of recurring responses can offer insight of philosophical significance. In this paper I exemplify the value of engaging with recurring but misguided popular objections by looking carefully at one such objection to my recent book, Is God a Delusion?
66. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Kai Draper Evidence without Priors
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I argue that it is possible to acquire evidence that has no probability, not even zero, prior to its acquisition. If I am right then, contrary to certain Bayesian models of confirmation, conditionalization is not the only possible basis upon which a rational agent will alter her credence in some hypothesis in response to new evidence. My conclusion follows from certain analyses of the Sleeping Beauty problem. Because those analyses are controversial, however, I alter the Sleeping Beauty scenario to generate an obvious example of evidence that has no prior probability.
67. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
M. Andrew Holowchak The ‘Soft Dictatorship’ of Reason: Freud on Religion, Science, and Utopia
68. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Yehuda Gellman A Problem for the Christian Mystical Doxastic Practice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
William Alston has identified what he calls a “Christian Mystical Practice” as one of the many doxastic practices in which humans engage. He defends CMP as being as rational as other doxastic practices, including the sense perceptual practice, having its own input and output rules, and its own background overrider system. I argue that there seems to be a serious problem with Alston’s characterization of the overrider system for CMP. The presence of this problem threatens to damage Alston’s argument for the rationality of engaging in the Christian Mystical Practice.
69. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Mark Bernstein Challenges and Defense
70. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Christopher H. Pearson Methodological Naturalism, Intelligent Design, and Lessons from the History of Embryology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Intelligent Design proponents consistently deny that science is rightfully governed by the norm of methodological naturalism—that independent of one’s actual metaphysical commitments regarding the natural/supernatural, a scientist, qua scientist, must behave as if the world is constituted by the natural, material world. This essay works to develop more fully a pragmatic justification for methodological naturalism, one that focuses on a number of key elements found in 17th and 18th century embryology.
71. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Joseph P. Li Vecchi Analogical Deduction via a Calculus of Predicables
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article identifies and formalizes the logical features of analogous terms that justify their use in deduction. After a survey of doctrines in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Cajetan, the criteria of “analogy of proper proportionality” are symbolized in first-order predicate logic. A common genus justifies use of a common term, but does not provide the inferential link required for deduction. Rather, the respective differentiae foster this link through their identical proportion. A natural-language argument by analogy is formalized so as to exhibit these criteria, thereby showing the validity of analogical deduction.
72. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
James Baillie New Problems for Religious Pluralism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
John Hick’s theory of religious pluralism posits the same ineffable spiritual reality, ‘the Real,’ as the source of all major religious traditions. He offers pluralism as the best explanation of salvific parity, the thesis that these religions are equally effective vehicles for salvation. Most criticisms of Hick have focused on the explanans, arguing that the Real cannot play any explanatory role due to its ineffability. I raise two difficulties for the explanandum, the thesis of salvific parity. I call these the problems of bad religion and good secularism.
73. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Rob Lovering The Problem of the Theistic Evidentialist Philosophers
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
That theistic evidentialist philosophers have failed to make the evidential case for theism to atheistic evidentialist philosophers raises a problem—a question to be answered. I argue here that—of the most plausible possible solutions to this problem—each is either inadequate or, when adequate, in conflict with the theistic evidentialist philosophers’ defining beliefs. I conclude that the problem of the theistic evidentialist philosophers—the question of why theistic evidentialist philosophers have failed to make their case to atheistic evidentialist philosophers—is a problem for theistic evidentialist philosophers—an objection to their defining beliefs.
74. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Bradley Monton Against Multiverse Theodicies
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In reply to the problem of evil, some suggest that God created an infinite number of universes—for example, that God created every universe that contains more good than evil. I offer two objections to these multiverse theodicies. First, I argue that, for any number of universes God creates, he could have created more, because he could have created duplicates of universes. Next, I argue that multiverse theodicies can’t adequately account for why God would create universes with pointless suffering, and hence they don’t solve the problem of evil.
75. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
David J. Anderson, Joshua L. Watson The Mystery of Foreknowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Many have attempted to respond to arguments for the incompatibility of freedom with divine foreknowledge by claiming that God’s beliefs about the future are explained by what the world is like at that future time. We argue that this response adequately advances the discussion only if the theist is able to articulate a model of foreknowledge that is both clearly possible and compatible with freedom. We investigate various models the theist might articulate and argue that all of these models fail.
76. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Aaron Segal, Alvin Plantinga Response to Churchland
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Paul Churchland argues that Plantinga’s evolutionary argument against naturalism is unsuccessful and so we need not accept its conclusion. In this paper, we respond to Churchland’s argument. After we briefly recapitulate Plantinga’s argument and state Churchland’s argument, we offer three objections to Churchland’s argument: (1) its first premise has little to recommend it, (2) its second premise is false, and (3) its conclusion is consistent with, and indeed entails, the conclusion of Plantinga’s argument.
77. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Evan Fales Divine Commands and Moral Obligation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A popular proof for the existence of God assumes that there are objective moral duties, arguing that this can only be explained by there being a supreme law-giver, namely God. The upshot is either a Divine Command Theory (DCT)—or something similar—or a natural-law theory. I discuss two prominent theories, Robert Adams’ DCT and Stephen Evans’ hybrid DCT/natural-law theory. I argue that they suffer from fatal difficulties. Natural-law theories are plausible, if God exists, but can’t be used to prove His existence; and are less plausible, on the evidence, than a naturalistic natural-law theory, which has the best prospects for providing an objective foundation for morality.
78. Philo: Volume > 13 > Issue: 2
Michael W. Hickson Conscientious Refusals without Conscience: Why Not?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I uncover and critically analyze a methodological assumption in the literature on conscientious refusals in health care. The assumption is what I call the “Priority of Conscience Principle,” which says the following: to determine the moral status of any act of conscientious refusal, it is first necessary to determine the nature and value of conscience. I argue that it is not always necessary to discuss conscience in the debate on conscientious refusals, and that discussing conscience is even problematic, since it can lead authors to beg the question.
79. Philo: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
J.L. Schellenberg A Reply to Wykstra
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Wykstra’s paper defends two objections to my reasoning in The Wisdom to Doubt. One says that we in fact do take evidence to be representative of all the relevant evidence that exists when forming the judgment that it makes some proposition probable, the other that our judgments as to the representativeness of evidence are often justified, and can be justified even in matters of religion. Both objections are instructive but ultimately unsuccessful, as I show here.
80. Philo: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Matthew Carey Jordan Metaphysical Naturalism and Some Moral Realisms
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I argue that morality as such is characterized by a number of distinctive features, and that metaphysical naturalists should believe that there are moral facts only if there is a plausible naturalistic explanation of the existence of facts which exemplify those features. I survey three prominent (and very different) naturalistic moral theories—the reductive naturalism of Peter Railton, Frank Jackson’s analytic descriptivism, and Christine Korsgaard’s Kantianism—and argue that none of them has the resources to explain the existence of genuine moral facts.