Displaying: 21-37 of 37 documents

0.177 sec

21. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 3 > Issue: 1/2/3
Hélène Bauer-Bernit Droit, langues et représentation des connaissances
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The connection between law, language and knowledge representation is evoked in its theoretical framework, in the light of recent developments in linguistics, philosophy, theory of law and congnitivescience on wich artificial intelligence is based. The conditions and limitations of the modelisation of law are examined. Conclusions are draw concerning the feasibility; usefulness and limitations of “trans-frontier” expert-systems.
22. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 3 > Issue: 1/2/3
Georges Kalinowski Sur l’analogie entre le déontique et l’aléthique: Logique des normes, logique déontique et leur analogie avec la logique modale alethique
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Since Leibniz, the logic of norms is founded on the analogy between the deontic and the alethic. Nevertheless, von Wright, creator of the deontic logic -firstly logic of norms, afterwards logic of normative statements-, holds this analogy responsible for the misadventures of the deontic logic. Now it is not responsible, but only limited so that the miscarriages in question are imputable solely to the overstepping of its limits.
23. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Jean Dhombres La Figure dans le Discours Géométrique: Les Façonnages d’un Style
24. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1/2
Lorenzo Peña De la logique combinatoire des ‘Generales Inquisitiones’ aux calculs combinatoires contemporains
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his 1686 essay GI Leibniz undertook to reduce sentences to noun-phrases, truth to being. Such a reduction arose from his equating proof with conceptual analysis. Within limits Leibniz’s logical calculus provides a reasonable way of surmounting the dichotomy, thus allowing a reduction of hypothetical to categorical statements. However it yields the disastrous result that, whenever A is possible and so is B, there can be an entity being both A and B. Yet, Leibniz was in the GI the forerunner of 20th century combinatory logic, which (successfully!) practices - sometimes for reasons not entirely unlike Leibniz’s own grounds - reductions of the same kinds he tried to carry out.
25. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1/2
Miguel Sánchez-Mazas Actualisation, développement et perfectionnement des calculs logiques arithmético-intensionnels de Leibniz
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In the parts I and II of this paper, the Author shows:1. how Leibniz’s arithmetico-intensional logical calculi of April 1679 can be completed and transformed in an intensional Boolean algebra (U, v, &:, -, e, -e) admitting, on the one hand, two different logical interpretations:li1: as a complete and consistent calculus of terms (properties) and syllogistic;li2: as a deontic first-order calculus and, on the other hand, two different arithmetical interpretations:ai1: as a numerical Boolean algebra (DM, lcm, ged, M/..., 1, M) of all divisors of a natural number M;ai2: as a numerlcal Boolean algebra (BA, lcbc, gcbc, A-..., 0, A) of all binary components of a natural number A.Arithmetical representations of negation of a term x and of combination (intensional conjunction) and alternative (intensional disjunction) of two or more terms are respectively M/x, lcm (lower common multiple) and gcd (greatest common divisor) in the first Boolean algebra (ai1) and A-x, lcbc (lower common binary composite) and gcbc (greatest common binary component) in the second one (ai2).2. that, in this context, each possible world U of 2ⁿ elements (terms, acts) can be defined on the basis on n elements of U choosen as “saturated” (intensionally maximal, but possible) in U or, inversely, on the basis of n elements of U choosen as “primitive” (intensionally minimal, but not-universal) in U. In fact, each possible element of U can be defined now as an alternative of saturated elements of U, now as a combination of primitive (opposite to saturated) elements of U; all combinations of saturated elements of U being equivalent to the impossible element (-e, non-entity, resp. impossible act) of U and an alternatives of elements of U being equivalent to the universal element (e, entity, resp. possible act) of U.In the arithmetical representation of each possible world U, the maximal number M (for ai1) or A (for ai2) represents the impossible (non existent) element of U. Now, each possihle world defined by n saturated (resp. primitive) elements can be automatically enlarged (restricted) by the introduction (suppression) of m new (old) saturated (resp. primitive) elements, producing a new possible world U’ where m impossible elements (centaur, pegasus, syren, unicorn, etc.) of U become possible elements of U’ or inversely.After this first type of arithmetical representation of logical calculi, where the terms are -as in Leibniz’s 1679 calculi- represented by natural numbers and the propositions by equations (for universal resp. prescriptive) or inequations (for particular, resp. permissive), in the part III the Author presents a second type of arithmetical representation where propositions are represented by natural numbers and the valid (classical or deontic) syllogisms by true arithmetical relations between the numbers of premisses and the number of conclusion. Here the entire syllogistic adopts the form of a multiplication table wherea syllogism is valid if and only if the lcm (in ai1 ) or the lcbc (in ai2) of the characterlstic numbers of the premisses is a multiple (in ai1) or a binary composite (in ai2) of the characteristic number of the conclusion.
26. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1/2
Cinquiéme Colloque de I’ARC: ‘Percevoir, Raisonner, Agir (Articulation des modèles cognitifs)’ (Nancy, 24-26 Mars 1992)
27. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1/2
Bicentenaire de Lavoisier (Paris, 3-6 Mai 1994)