Displaying: 241-260 of 930 documents

0.232 sec

241. Augustinianum: Volume > 31 > Issue: 2
F. Vattioni 3 (1) Re 12, 10; 2 Par (Cr) 10, 10 e Teodoreto di Ciro
242. Augustinianum: Volume > 31 > Issue: 2
Vittorino Grossi L’auctoritas di Agostino nella dottrina del «peccatum originis» da Cartagine (418) a Trento (1546)
243. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 1
Maria Grazia Mara Agostino e la polemica Antimanichea: il ruolo di Paolo e del suo epistolario
244. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 1
Francesco Vattioni Note di onomastica punica nell’epistolario agostiniano: (EP. 17,2; 29,12)
245. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 1
Carlo Tibiletti Nota in margine a idolatria eresia e filolsofia in Tertulliano
246. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 1
Enrico dal Covolo Ancora Sulla “Statua of Sant’Ippolito”: Per una “messa a punto” dei rapporti tra i Severi e il cristianesimo
247. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Marialuisa Annecchino Manni Iob 14,4-5¹ nella lettura dei Padri
248. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Ugo Bianchi Le origini dello gnosticismo: Nuovi studi e ricerche
249. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Ubaldo Pizzani Qualche osservazione sul concetto di armonia cosmica in Agostino e Cassiodoro alla luce di Sap 11,21(20)
250. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Sever J. Voicu Un frammento copto dell’omelia cattedrale 77 di Severo d’Antiochia
251. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Alberto Camplani La Quaresima egiziana nel VII secolo: note di cronologia su Mon. Epiph. 77, Manchester Ryland Suppl. 47-48, P. Grenf. II 112, P. Berol. 10677, P. Köln 215 e un’omelia copta
252. Augustinianum: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
José Pablo Martín La saggezza creatrice secondo Teofilo d’Antiochia ed i suoi silenzi cristologici
253. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Paolo Siniscalco Sulla composizione delle comunità cristiane in Africa all’inizio deI V secolo secondo il De catechizandis rudibus di Agostino
254. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Giancarlo Rinaldi Diodoro di Tarso, Antiochia e Ie ragioni della polemica antiallegorista
255. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Manlio Simonetti Due note agostiniane
256. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Maria Grazia Mara L’itinerario dell’uomo secondo Agostino: da “spirituale” a “carnale”, da “carnale” a “spirituale”
257. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Vittorino Grossi Presentazione
258. Augustinianum: Volume > 33 > Issue: 1/2
Enrico dal Covolo Bibliografia italiana di mariologia patristica (1962-1992)
259. Augustinianum: Volume > 61 > Issue: 1
Angelo Segneri Spigolature pseudodidimiane
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The present study, after a quick codicological investigation of the two surviving manuscripts of the De trinitate by pseudo-Didymus, in which it is concluded that one is a copy of the other, focuses on the lexical analysis of the first book of the mutilated trinitarian treatise. By showing divergences from the authentic works of Didymus, alongside parallels with the writings of the Cappadocian Fathers, Cyril of Alexandria, Theodoret, of other late patristic authors, as well as with those of the Neoplatonic philosophers, in particular Proclus, the author concludes that the chronological position of De trinitate should not be before the end of the 5th century, and suggests a possible origin from an environment of Antiochene influence.
260. Augustinianum: Volume > 61 > Issue: 1
Nello Cipriani Il De immortalitate animae di Agostino nella critica più recente
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In De immortalitate animae Augustine is not satisfied with completing his proof of the immortality of the soul – which had been left open in the second book of the Soliloquies –; he also answers some possible objections, demonstrating that the rational soul cannot cease to exist, it cannot die, nor can it change into an irrational body or soul. Furthermore, remaining faithful to the programmatic declaration of never wanting to stray from the authority of Christ (Acad. 3, 20, 43), he specifies the ontological status of the soul by affirming that it is, in itself, mutable and therefore not of a divine nature, as Varro had argued. Nor is it a substance foreign to the body, as the Platonists claimed, because the soul has an appetitus ad corpus and, if it questions itself, it easily discovers that it desires nothing else «except to do something, to know with intelligence or with the senses, or only to live, as far as this is in its power» (nisi agendi aliquid, aut sciendi, aut sentiendi, aut tantummodo vivendi in quantum sua illi potestas est).