Displaying: 21-40 of 1818 documents

0.106 sec

21. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Julia Annas Comments on John Doris’s Lack of Character
22. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Jordi Fernández Self-Knowledge, Rationality and Moore’s Paradox
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I offer a model of self-knowledge that provides a solution to Moore’s paradox. First, I distinguish two versions of the paradox and I discuss two approaches to it, neither of which solves both versions of the paradox. Next, I propose a model of self-knowledge according to which, when I have a certain belief, I form the higher-order belief that I have it on the basis of the very evidence that grounds my first-order belief. Then, I argue that the model in question can account for both versions of Moore’s paradox. Moore’s paradox, I conclude, tells us something about our conceptions of rationality and self-knowledge. For it teaches us that we take it to be constitutive of being rational that one can have privileged access to one’s own mind and it reveals that having privileged access to one’s own mind is a matter of forming first-order beliefs and corresponding second-order beliefs on the same basis.
23. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
James A. Woodbridge Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair
24. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Nomy Arpaly Comments on Lack of Character by John Doris
25. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Graham Priest Words Without Knowledge
26. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Dorothy Edgington The Mystery of the Missing Boundary
27. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Alan H. Goldman Reason Internalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper defends strong internalism about reasons, the view that reasons must relate to pre-existing motivational states, from several kinds of counterexamples, supposed desire independent reasons, that have been proposed. A central distinction drawn is that between there being a reason and an agent’s having a reason. For an agent to have an F reason, she must be F-minded. Reasons, as what motivate us, are states of affairs and not themselves desires or motivational states, but they must connect to existing motivational states. It has been claimed that rationality itself requires us to recognize certainreasons independent of our desires, that we acquire new desires by learning what is valuable, by acquiring desire-independent reasons to pursue certain values. It is claimed also that prudential and moral reasons are desire independent. By offering an account of rationality as coherence, by appealing to broader concerns as opposed to specific desires, and by appealing to the distinction noted above, the paper exposes weaknesses in recent arguments for desire independent reasons by Millgram, Smith, Korsgaard, and Searle. The reasons they propose can be interpreted as internal (not desire independent) or dismissed as nonexistent.
28. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Lucy O’Brien Self-knowledge, Agency and Force
29. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Acknowledgments
30. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Recent Publications
31. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
John M. Doris Précis of Lack of Character
32. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Roy Sorensen Précis of Vagueness and Contradiction
33. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Peter Forrest Universals as Sense-data
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper concerns the structure of appearances. I argue that to be appeared to in a certain way is to be aware of one or more universals. Universals therefore function like the sense-data, once highly favoured but now out of fashion. For instance, to be appeared to treely, in a visual way, is to be aware of the complex relation, being treeshaped and tree-coloured and being in front of, a relation of a kind which could be instantiated by a material object and a perceiver, which is thus instantiated in the veridical case but not in the non-veridical.
34. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 71 > Issue: 3
Robert C. Solomon “What’s Character Got to Do with It?”
35. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Christopher S. Hill Replies to Marian David, Anil Gupta, and Keith Simmons
36. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Anil Gupta Remarks on Christopher Hill’s Thought and World
37. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Igal Kvart A Probabilistic Theory of Knowledge
38. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Andy Egan Secondary Qualities and Self-Location
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
There is a strong pull to the idea that there is some metaphysically interesting distinction between the fully real, objective, observer-independent qualities of things as they are in themselves, and the less-than-fully-real, subjective, observer-dependent qualities of things as they are for us. Call this (putative) distinction the primary/secondary quality distinction. The distinction between primary and secondary qualities is philosophically interesting because it is (a) often quite attractive to draw such a distinction, and (b) incredibly hard to spell it out in any kind of satisfying and sensible way. I attempt such a spelling-out after first trying to pin down in more detail what we want from the primary/secondary quality distinction, and saying a bit about why that is such a hard thingto get.
39. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Stathis Psillos What Do Powers Do When They Are Not Manifested?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In the present paper, I offer a conceptual argument against the view that all properties are pure powers. I claim that thinking of all properties as pure powers leads to a regress. The regress, I argue, can be solved only if non-powers are admitted. The kernel of my thesis is that any attempt to answer the title question in an informative way will undermine a pure-power view of properties. In particular, I focus my critique on recent arguments in favour of pure powers by the Late George Molnar and Jennifer McKitrick. The lines of defence of the friends of powers converge on what I call 'the ultimate argument for powers', viz., that current physics entails (or supports) the view that the fundamental properties (spin, mass, charge) are ungrounded powers. I take issue with this argument and make a modest suggestion: that the evidence from current physics is inconclusive.
40. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 72 > Issue: 1
Robert J.Howell Self-Knowledge and Self-Reference
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Self-Knowledge and Self-Reference is a defense and reconciliation of the two apparently conflicting theses that the self is peculiarly elusive and that our basic, cogito-judgments are certain. On the one hand, Descartes seems to be correct that nothing is more certain than basic statements of self-knowledge, such as "I am thinking." On the other hand, there is the compelling Humean observation that when we introspect, nothing is found except for various "impressions." The problem, then, is that the Humean and Cartesian insights are both initially appealing, yet they appear to be in tension with one another. In this paper I attempt to satisfy both intuitions by developing a roughly descriptivist account of self-reference according to which our certainty in basic beliefs stems precisely from our needing to know so little in order to have them.