Displaying: 181-200 of 1911 documents

0.148 sec

181. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 14 > Issue: 3
William J. Peace, Claire Roy Scrutinizing Ashley X: Presumed Medical “Solutions” vs. Real Social Adaptation
182. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 1
Mark Amadeus Notturno Falsifiability Revisited: Popper, Daubert, and Kuhn
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The Supreme Court’s 1993 Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals decision acknowledged a change in the Federal Rules of Evidence for the admissibility of expert scientific testimony in legal proceedings. Two of the most controversial aspects of the decision were the Court’s general comments about science, and its appeal to Karl Popper’s notion of falsifiability as “a key question to be answered in determining whether a theory or technique is scientific knowledge that will assist the trier of fact.” Indeed, Chief Justice Rehnquist acknowledged in his dissenting opinion that he did not know what falsifiability meant and that he thought other judges would not understand it either. This paper explains what Popper meant by falsifiability, why it has been misunderstood, why it is important today, and how the Court’s decision reflects the larger move from foundationalism to fallibilism that has taken place in epistemology over the course of the twentieth century.
183. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 1
Tony Ward An English Daubert? Law, Forensic Science and Epistemic Deference
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A test for the admissibility of expert evidence, partly derived from Daubert, has recently been introduced into English criminal law by the unusual mechanism of aPractice Direction.This article compares the Daubert trilogy and the English Practice Direction as responses to the problem of epistemic deference by juries to experts. Juries areoften justified in deferring to experts as to the relevance of the underlying evidence examined by the expert, including what inferences can be drawn from it. There is a concern, however, that juries may also defer to experts’ claims about the weight of their own evidence: how strongly or confidently those inferences can be stated. Overly deferential jurors may place excessive weight on forensic science evidence that rests on shaky foundations. The new English admissibility regime (drawing on recommendations by the Law Commission) appears better tailored than Daubert to address this issue about the strength of inferences presented by expert witnesses. As a result, however, it places considerable demands in judges, advocates and expert witnesses, and how successful it will be in practice remains to be seen.
184. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 1
Jason Borenstein, Carol Henderson Reflections on Daubert: A Look Back at the Supreme Court’s Decision
185. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 1
Daniella McCahey, Simon A. Cole Human(e) Science? Demarcation, Law, and ‘Scientific Whaling’ in Whaling in the Antarctic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper analyzes a recent case in which a court, like the Daubert Court, was asked to demarcate legitimate from illegitimate science. The court was the International Court of Justice (ICJ), and it was asked by the state of Australia to find the state of Japan in violation of the International Convention for the Regulation of Whaling because of its licensing of a research program that engaged in killing whales ostensibly “for purposes of scientific research.” Australia premised a good portion of its argument on a four-part definition of “scientific research,” reminiscent of the four notorious “Daubert criteria,” and the claim that the Japanese research program, “JARPA II,” failed to comply with this definition. The paper suggests that the Court’s judgment, which forced Japan to temporarily cease whaling, illustrates the merits for courts of avoiding the temptation to engage in demarcation exercises.
186. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 2
Roger Stanev Data and Safety Monitoring Board and the Ratio Decidendi of the Trial
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Current decision-making by a Data and Safety Monitoring Board (DSMB) regarding clinical trial conduct is intricate, largely limited by cases and rules, and essentially secretive. Decision-making by court of law, by contrast, although also intricate and largely constrained by cases and rules, is essentially public. In this paper, I argue by analogy that legal decision-making, which strives for a balance between competing demands of conservatism and innovation, supplies a good basis to the logic behind DSMB decision-making. Using the doctrine of precedents in legal reasoning as my central analog will lead us to an analogy for much more systematic documentation and transparency of decisions in clinical trials. My conclusion is twofold: every DSMB decision should articulate a clear general principle (a ratio decidendi) that gives reason for the decision; and all such decisions should be made public. I use reported DSMB experiences of the Women’s Health Initiative Clinical Trials to illustrate my analogical argument.
187. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 15 > Issue: 3
Carl Mitcham Book Review: Wendell Wallach’s A Dangerous Master: How to Keep Technology from Slipping Beyond Our Control
188. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 16 > Issue: 1
Clifton Perry Different Mistakes in the Law and the Difference They Make
189. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 16 > Issue: 2
Sarah Lucy Cooper Forensic Science Identification Evidence: Tensions Between Law and Science
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
For decades, courtrooms around the world have admitted evidence from forensic science analysts, such as fingerprint, tool-mark and bite-mark examiners, in order to solve crimes. Scientific progress, however, has led to significant criticism of the ability of such disciplines to engage in individualization i.e., “match” suspects exclusively to evidence. Despite this, American courts largely reject legal challenges based on arguments that identification evidence provided by these forensic science disciplines is unreliable. In so holding, these courts affirm precedent that it is the adversarial system’s function to weed out frailties in forensic evidence, and find that criticism of the forensic sciences lacks sui generis qualities. This article provides an independent critique of relevant American case law, from which three themes emerge. These themes are (1) the law’s misuse of science; (2) law’s scepticism towards change; and (3) law’s narrow construction of rationality, which generates reductionist concepts, and divorces science from its social context. As such, this article shows how the American judiciary’s approach to this global issue provides a contemporary illustration of key institutional tensions between science and law, and offers some recommendations for reforms that aim to facilitate the legal process to utilize the most reliable forensic science evidence possible.
190. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Michelle R. Detwiler Balancing Scientific Freedom and National Security after September 11th
191. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Bryn Williams-Jones Commercial Surrogacy and the Redefinition of Motherhood
192. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 3
Brent Garland Bioethics and Bioterrorism
193. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 4
Richard Haigh, Mirko Bagaric Immortality and Sentencing Law
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The time may not be far away where we may be able to live much longer than we do now – potentially forever. This will have an enormous impact on the way people live their lives as the underlying premise that life is finite underpins many of the central decisions and life choices we make. This paper outlines some philosophical and legal doctrines that are based on the premise that life is finite and some of the changes that may need to occur in light of medical advances in ageing. In particular, it focuses on the changes to sentencing law that may be necessary to accommodate increased human longevity. For the skeptics who refuse to accept the concept of immortality, the arguments presented do not depend on living forever. Some of the issues discussed here are also relevant, albeit in an attenuated manner, because of increases in human longevity that have occurred in the last 100 years.Babies born 30 years hence may grow up with such perfect cellular maintenance that they will never age, dying only by accident or choice. Will we get the benefits of these discoveries? Maybe not – we might be, sadly, the last mortal generation. But who knows – if we can keep ourselves alive and healthy, maybe some of these treatments will be retrofitted into our ailing bodies and make us new again.... If you are lucky you may see 3000, or even live indefinitely. We need to discuss, well ahead of time, whether that would be desirable. Me, I’m voting for life over death.
194. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 5
Susanne B. Haga, Joann A. Boughman Are Health Professionals Prepared for the Task of Integrating Genetics into Healthcare?: A National Conference Considers the Question
195. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 5
Norman K. Swazo For “Just Results”: Questioning National Missile Defense Research in Alaska
196. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 6
Kimarie R. Stratos David Guston’s Between Politics and Science: Assuring the Integrity and Productivity of Research
197. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 2 > Issue: 7
Jennifer Douglas-Vidas, Marsha E. Reichman What Role Should Rules, Guidelines, and Education Play in the Responsible Conduct of Research?: A National Conference Addresses the Issue
198. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 3 > Issue: 1
David B. Resnik A Biotechnology Patent Pool: An Idea Whose Time Has Come?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper discusses the idea of forming a patent pool in order to address some of the licensing problems in the biotechnology industry. The pool would be an independent, non-profit corporation that would manage patents and have the authority to grant licenses. The patent pool would not be a purely altruistic venture, since it would charge licensing fees. The pool would charge the market price for licensing services and reimburse patent holders for licensing activities. The pool would also provide patent holders with a minimum income based on a percentage of royalties generated from the pool. The pool would include patents on a variety of materials and methods that play an important role in biotechnology. It would also be international in scope, with the power to grant licenses in different countries.
199. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 3 > Issue: 1
Doug Jesseph James Franklin’s The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability before Pascal
200. The Journal of Philosophy, Science & Law: Volume > 3 > Issue: 2
William J. FitzPatrick, Lee L. Zwanziger Defending Against Biochemical Warfare: Ethical Issues Involving the Coercive Use of Investigational Drugs and Biologics in the Military