Displaying: 181-200 of 1482 documents

0.471 sec

181. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Dale Parker The Prologue of the Protagoras as a School of Dialectic
182. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Maria Pavlou Socrates as Scamander in Plato’s Protagoras
183. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Chloe Balla Sailing Away from Antilogic: Plato’s Phaedo 90b-101e
184. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Georgia Mouroutsou Choosing a Life and Rejecting a Thoughtless Life in Philebus 20-22
185. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Brian Apicella Theaetetus 201c-210b: The Midwifery of Knowledge
186. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Robert Mayhew Theophrastus on the Mistletoe in De causis plantarum ii 17, and What It Tells Us about Aristotle’s Historia animalium viii(ix)
187. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Patrick Grafton-Cardwell Understanding Mediated Predication in Aristotle’s CategoriesPatrick Grafton-Cardwell
188. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim Aristotle’s NE ix 9 on Why the Happy Person Needs Friends
189. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Samuel Meister Aristotle on the Relation between Substance and Essence
190. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Jeremy Reid Changing the Laws of the Laws
191. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 41 > Issue: 2
Jamie Dow Beware of Imitations!: Aristotle and the Paradox of Fiction
192. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
William H. F. Altman Xenophon and Plato’s Meno
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Not only was it a reference to Ismenias the Theban (Men. 90a4-5) that allowed nineteenth-century scholars to establish a date of composition for Plato’s Meno on the basis of Xenophon’s Hellenica but beginning with “Meno the Thessalian” himself, immortalized as a scoundrel in Xenophon’s Anabasis, each of the four characters in Plato’s dialogue is shown to have a Xenophontic resonance, thus revealing Meno to be Plato’s tombeau de Xénophon.
193. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Francesca Alesse The Predicative Role of ‘Being Good’ in Aristotle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The article proposes a renewed analysis of the texts in which Aristotle claims that the term ‘good’ is spoken of in many ways and more precisely in as many ways as there are categories. After a revision of the traditional interpretations, a new reading of the texts is advanced in the light of the theory of predication described in Top. 103 b20-38 and Metaph. 1017 a7-30. The conclusion is that in the Aristotelian passages on the multivocity of ‘good’, the word ‘good’ should not be meant as the predicate of categorially distinct realities, and therefore as a qualifying adjective, but itself as the subject of the question what is it? (τί ἐστι;) In this way, it is possible to advance the hypothesis that the homonymous notion of ‘good’ performs a predicative function, useful to the formulation of practical and prescriptive propositions.
194. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Javier Aoiz, Marcelo D. Boeri The Genealogy of Justice and Laws in Epicureanism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, we argue that the Epicurean genealogy of justice and laws presuppose an analysis of the just as a modality of the useful, an approach that denies the conventional character of justice. This genealogical pattern differentiates the origin of justice from that of the law and refers to friendship as a relevant explanatory factor of the origin of justice. We maintain that the interpretations that underline the incoherence of this reference to friendship, in the framework of a hedonistic theory, presuppose a non-Epicurean sharp distinction between altruism and selfishness.
195. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Luc Brisson, Salomon Ofman The Mathematical Anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In Plato’s eponymous dialogue, Timaeus, the main character presents the universe as an (almost) perfect sphere filled by tiny, invisible particles having the form of four regular polyhedrons. At first glance, such a construction may seem close to an atomistic theory. However, one does not find any text in Antiquity that links Timaeus’ cosmology to the atomists, while Aristotle opposes clearly Plato to the latter. Nevertheless, Plato is commonly presented in contemporary literature as some sort of atomist, sometimes as supporting a form of so-called ‘mathematical atomism’. However, the term ‘atomism’ is rarely defined when applied to Plato. Since it covers many different theories, it seems that this term has almost as different meanings as different authors. The purpose of this article is to consider whether it is correct to connect Timaeus’ cosmology to some kind of ‘atomism’, however this term may be understood. Its purpose is double: to obtain a better understanding of the cosmology of the Timaeus, and to consider the different modern ‘atomistic’ interpretations of this cosmology. In short, we would like to show that such a claim, in any form whatsoever, is misleading, an impediment to the understanding of the dialogue, and more generally of Plato’s philosophy.
196. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Evan Coulter Mind and Necessity in Timaeus’ Hepatology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Analogies between the human and the cosmos run throughout Plato’s Timaeus. Timaeus claims that the cosmos came to be as mind’s “persuasion of necessity.” This paper argues that an anthropological equivalent to this “persuasion” can be found in Timaeus’ suggestive account of the human liver. Mediating between intellect and desire, the organ shows the problem of mind and necessity reflected in the human soul.
197. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Javier Echeñique Sosa, Jose Antonio Errazuriz Besa Aristotle on Personal Enmity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper we develop Aristotle’s remarks about personal enmity (ἔχθρα) into a systematic account, with a view to determining whether personal enmity has a role to play in the good life. We argue that such an account can be obtained by examining Aristotle’s claims about hatred, and that this examination reveals that there is a significant place for enmity in Aristotle’s conception of the good life.
198. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Andy German Progressus ad Infinitum?: A Theme in the Protagoras
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, I argue that in the “Great Speech” of the Protagoras, Plato investigates the consequences of a view of history as progress away from nature, as expressed in Protagoras’ account of humanity’s origin and development. Socrates’ hedonistic calculus, in the dialogue’s second half, confronts Protagoras with the full implications of his view - showing how, absent a doctrine of natural human perfections, progress necessarily devours its own tail.
199. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Mariana Gardella Aristotle on Riddle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Aristotle presents two different approaches to riddle in the Poetics and the Rhetoric. In this paper, I intend to argue that, despite meaningful differences, these two views on riddle are not contradictory, but rather complementary. Taken together, they provide a valuable explanation of the structure, as well as the cognitive function, of riddle.
200. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Albert Joosse Anchoring Innovation in the Platonic Axiochus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
As the youngest work in the Platonic corpus, the Axiochus interacts with other texts in the corpus as well as with its contemporary philosophical milieu. How it does so, however, and what the purpose of the work is, is still unclear. This paper proposes a new theoretical approach to this text, arguing that the Axiochus anchors a number of innovations. It discusses three innovations in particular: the introduction of philosophical therapy in Platonism, the use of Epicurean arguments in Academic philosophy, and a renovated Platonism on the contemporary philosophical scene. The Axiochus aims, so this paper argues, to make these innovations acceptable to different audiences by anchoring them in the Socratic dialogue and the therapeutic paradigm of philosophy, respectively.