Displaying: 181-200 of 1867 documents

0.178 sec

181. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 2
Elizabeth Anscombe Thought and Reality
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this essay, Anscombe describes the Aristotelian account of how the intellect makes actually intelligible the forms of material particulars, and thereby is able to fashion concepts and think of those things. She identifies difficulties in it having to do with the differing “content” of concepts and of forms, and the generality of the former. She then contrasts that account with the Lockean theory of ideas as representations and with Hume’s development of the ideational view which holds that all we can ever conceive of are ideas and impressions. She next compares the Aristotelian isomorphist account with that of Wittgenstein in the Tractatus, showing that while both avoid the sceptical implication of the theory of ideas, a question arises regarding the relation of names to their bearers and how to understand ostensible names. Finally, Anscombe outlines Anselm’s treatment of “nothing” but notes its limits as a general treatment. (Ed. J.H.)
182. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 2
John Zeis Anscombe and the Metaphysics of Human Action
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In “Causality and Determination,” Anscombe rejects the two received opinions on the nature of causality in the modern philosophical tradition. She rejects the Humean conception of universal generalization based on the constant conjunction in experience of cause and effect, and she also rejects the notion that causality entails a necessary connection between cause and effect. As an alternative, she suggests that the core notion of causality is one of the derivativeness of the effect from the cause. Her consideration of causality ranges generally over all types of causality, but I believe that the most significant implication of her position is in application to the causality of human action. In this paper, I will articulate what I take to be that position.
183. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 2
Photo of Elizabeth Anscombe
184. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 2
John Finnis On Anscombe’s “Royal Road” to True Belief 
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This essay draws upon observations made by Elizabeth Anscombe regarding, respectively, the mutual need of scientific theory and philosophical analysis, the manner in which human rationality may show itself as a principle of bodily action, and the fulfilment in the New Testament of the central promise of Hebrew scripture. It examines something of the nature of material organization and the incorporation and subsumption of that into living systems, among which emerges the human, rational form of life. Noting the distinctness of the human soul as a principle of thought, reflection, and free choice, certain aspects of scripture are identified and explored to suggest what Anscombe may, or might well, have had in mind in speaking of a “royal road.”
185. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 2
John Haldane Anscombe and Geach on Mind and Soul
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Anscombe and Geach were among the most interesting philosophers to have come out of Oxford in the twentieth century. Even before they encountered Wittgenstein, they had begun to distinguish themselves from their contemporaries, and in the course of their work they moved between highly abstract and often technical issues, and themes familiar to non-academics, the latter aptly illustrated by the title of Geach’s first collection of essays, God and the Soul, and by that of Anscombe’s analysis of human sexual acts, “Contraception and Chastity.” I consider their early work together and illustrate its influence on later writings by each. I then examine the ideas and arguments advanced in those writings in so far as they bear upon the issue of materialism and the question of the existence and nature of the soul. Finally, I respond to their somewhat skeptical arguments, though I conclude that there is also reason to acknowledge the propriety of what I will term “spiritual agnosticism.”
186. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Gregory P. Floyd Heidegger and Theology. By Judith Wolfe
187. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Michael Rota A Better Version of Pascal’s Wager
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The standard version of Pascal’s Wager suffers from serious problems. In this paper I present a modified version of a Wager-style argument that avoids several of the most serious objections to the standard version, viz., the objections of Duff and Hájek relating to infinite utilities, moral objections concerning the use of pragmatic considerations, and the many-gods objection. I argue that a serious commitment to living a Christian life is rational (and the failure to make such a commitment is irrational) if one is rational in assigning a credence to Christianity of at least one-half. The upshot is that considerations of practical rationality dramatically lower the bar for natural theology.
188. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Gaven Kerr, OP Aquinas, Stump, and the Nature of a Simple God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In order for God to be simple, He must be esse itself, but in some texts Aquinas seems to distinguish between esse and id quod est, so it seems that God cannot be an id quod est. To resolve this tension, Eleonore Stump proposes quantum theology, whereby we are able to attribute contradictory predicates to a thing of which we have no quidditative knowledge; so God then can be seen as esse itself and as an ens. In this paper I criticise this approach and hold that there is a principled philosophical approach that we can take to these matters through a greater clarification of what it means for God to be pure esse. It is seen that this latter approach entails that God is indeed an ens, so that the ens-hood of God is derived from His being pure esse, in which case quantum theology is not needed for a Thomistic resolution of the problem.
189. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Kevin E. O’Reilly, OP The Temporality of Prudence in Thomas Aquinas: Towards a Participatory Construal of Heidegger’s Sorge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to Heidegger’s interpretation, while Aristotle’s treatment of practical wisdom cannot be divorced from his account of theoretical wisdom, there has nevertheless been a tendency in Western thought to separate what he terms the theoretical and practical modes of concern and to afford a certain priority to the theoretical mode. This article argues that one thinker in the tradition with which Heidegger engaged, namely Thomas Aquinas, constitutes an exception to this analysis. Thomas’s treatment of prudence (prudentia), rooted in Aristotle’s discussion of phronēsis, furnishes an initial point of contact with Heidegger. Turning to Thomas’s account of the precepts of the natural law, I show that implicit therein is an understanding of care that corresponds to Heidegger’s notion of Sorge, albeit an understanding that is imbued with a strikingly different character—namely, a theistic one. Central to this argument is the claim that Thomas escapes Heidegger’s dismissal of ontotheology thanks to his analogical construal of being.
190. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Philip Neri Reese, OP Supertranscendentality and Metaphysics: An Aporia in the Thought of John Duns Scotus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article investigates an aporia in the metaphysical thought of John Duns Scotus. On the one hand, there are strong textual grounds for saying that according to Scotus the subject matter of metaphysics excludes logical being. On this reading, metaphysics would be a transcendental, but not a supertranscendental, science. On the other hand, there are strong textual grounds for saying that according to Scotus the subject matter of metaphysics includes logical being. On this reading, metaphysics would be a supertranscendental, and not just a transcendental, science. Two possible paths for resolving this aporia are considered and subsequently problematized. The aporia seems to be genuine, and recognition of this fact brings into sharper focus the position of Scotus’s metaphysics in the development of supertranscendental thought.
191. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Michael Winter To Flourish or Destruct: A Personalist Theory of Human Goods, Motivations, Failure, and Evil. By Christian Smith
192. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Christopher M. Brown Mind, Truth and Teleology: An Introduction to Scholastic Philosophy. By John Peterson
193. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
James M. Jacobs The Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas: A Sketch. By Stephen L. Brock
194. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Paul St. Amour The Eclipse and Recovery of Beauty: A Lonergan Approach. By John D. Dadosky
195. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Maria Fedoryka “Finis superabundant operis”: Refining an Ancient Cause for Explaining the Conjugal Act
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Dietrich von Hildebrand denominated the generation of new human life as the “superabundant end” of the spousal act not to deny but to refine the scholastic view that the child is the “end of the act,” simply. The act at the source of human generation is not straightforwardly generative; rather, its generativity is metaphysically grounded in it as a concrete act of union between the spouses. There are thus in some sense two finalities structuring the act, with a specific order between them: union and the fruitfulness following superabundantly from it. In this essay I bring to evidence the framework underlying von Hildebrand’s position by examining love as the forma of the spousal act and the significance of sexuality as an embodied act. I will conclude with some thoughts on how the concept of superabundance accommodates certain truths about the spousal act more readily than does the simple notion of finality.
196. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
John J. Conley, SJ Reforming the Art of Living. By Rico Vitz
197. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Antonio Ramos Díaz How Not to Argue against Materialism: On Oderberg’s Storage Problem Argument
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The storage problem is the problem of explaining how concepts could be stored in the mind if the mind is something material. David Oderberg has defended the immateriality of the human intellect on the basis of the storage problem. The general idea of the argument is that concepts possess features that make them categorially incapable of being stored in any material locus. Yet, they are stored in the mind. Hence, the mind is immaterial. In this paper I propose that Oderberg’s argument cannot be accepted. First, I argue that on one reading the argument leads to absurdity and is inconsistent with Oderberg’s Thomism. Secondly, I argue that even on another, weaker reading of the argument, Oderberg has no plausible and adequate grounds for accepting it, and the grounds he does provide in favor of the argument seem in tension with Thomism.
198. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 3
Travis Dumsday The Problem of Divine Hiddenness: Is the Devil in the Details?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The problem of divine hiddenness is, along with the problem of evil, one of the two principal arguments for atheism in the current literature. Very roughly: If God really existed, then He would make His reality rationally indubitable to everyone (or at least everyone willing to engage Him in relationship). Since that hasn’t happened, God does not exist. Among the many replies made to this argument, a basic distinction might be drawn between (1) those made from within generic theism (theism prescinding from any specific religion), and (2) those made from within a definite faith tradition and employing the distinctive doctrinal resources of that tradition. That same division is apparent in the literature on the problem of evil, and among faith-specific work on that problem, one idea occasionally entertained (especially in the context of natural evil) is that the reality of evil spiritual beings may play a role in a defence or theodicy. Heretofore no one has imported that idea into the debate over hiddenness. In this paper I try out several versions of this strategy, eventually arguing that for those branches of Christianity with a doctrinal commitment to the reality of fallen angels, novel responses to the hiddenness problem are thereby made available. It is clearly a response unlikely to persuade atheists, but for Christians willing to consider the problem from within a distinctively Christian perspective it may carry some force. It may likewise be of use to those less concerned about countering atheism and more concerned with simply answering the longstanding theological question of why God might properly permit rational doubt in His reality.
199. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 4
Steven J. Jensen Our Search With Socrates for Moral Truth (Gary Michael Atkinson)
200. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 4
Raymond Hain Knowing the Natural Law: From Precepts and Inclinations to Deriving Oughts (Steven J. Jensen)