Displaying: 181-200 of 4007 documents

0.174 sec

181. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 2
Craig A. Condella Heidegger’s Volk: Between National Socialism and Poetry
182. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 2
Michael Gorman Independence and Substance
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The paper takes up a traditional view that has also been a part of some recent analytic metaphysics, namely, the view that substance is to be understood in terms of independence. Taking as my point of departure some recent remarks by Kit Fine, I propose reviving the Aristotelian-scholastic idea that the sense in which substances are independent is that they are non-inherent, and I do so by developing a broad notion of inherence that is more usable in the context of contemporary analytic metaphysics than the traditional notion is. I end by showing how non-inherence, while necessary for being a substance, cannot be taken as sufficient without some qualifying remarks.
183. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 2
John R. Fortin The Naming of Father and Son in Saint Anselm’s Monologion 38–42
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
For Saint Anselm, the mystery of the Holy Trinity was not merely an object of intellectual speculation but, more importantly, the object of praise and worship. Even though he claims that there is nothing in his treatise that violates the teachings of the Fathers, especially that of Augustine, Anselm explores in Monologion the doctrine of the Trinity in his own unique style. One very interesting discussion that does not appear in Augustine’s De Trinitate or in any of the Augustinian corpus is found in chapter 42, in which Anselm argues for the propriety of naming the Supreme Spirit “Father” and His Word “Son.” This paper examines this chapter, first, in the context of the four immediately preceding chapters and, second, in the context of those writings of Augustine that might have influenced Anselm in his presentation. The paper then offers reasons why Anselm included this unique chapter in his discussion on the Trinity.
184. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
G. R. Evans Medieval Education
185. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Gary Atkinson Potential Being and the Source of Cosmic Order
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper argues (a) that the concept of “potential being” is central to the theory and practice of contemporary cosmology and evolutionary science, and (b) that the reality of potential being points to the existence of an intelligent and purposive cause of the intelligible order among potential beings that existed from the first moments of the Big Bang. The paper introduces and explains the concept of “potential being” and then traces the existence of potential beings back to the beginnings of the cosmos at the instant of the Big Bang. This primeval existence of potential beings is shown to possess a character and order that points to a cause external to that order. The paper concludes with a consideration of the features that must be possessed by that external cause in order to make sense of what we know.
186. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Michael Rohlf Kant’s Transcendental Proof of Realism
187. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Michael F. Wagner Troubling Play: Meaning and Entity in Plato’s Parmenides
188. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Gregory T. Doolan Philosophy, God and Motion
189. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. The Chronicles of Narnia and Philosophy
190. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Adrian Bardon The Aristotelian Prescription: Skepticism, Retortion, and Transcendental Arguments
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
From a number of quarters have come attempts to answer some form of skepticism—about knowledge of the external world, freedom of the will, or moral reasons—by showing it to be performatively self-defeating. Examples of this strategy are subject to the criticism that they fail to shift the burden of proof from the anti-skeptical position, and so fail to establish the epistemic entitlement they seek. To these approaches I contrast one way of understanding Kant’s core anti-skeptical arguments in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant’s goal is the more modest one of showing the applicability of the concepts of substance and cause to experience, against those who might call such application incoherent or a category mistake. I explain why this goal makes Kant’s approach more promising than those of neo-Kantian practitioners of otherwise structurally-similar strategies.
191. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Brendan Palla Notices
192. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Scott F. Aikin Modest Evidentialism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Evidentialism is the view that subjects should believe neither more than nor contrary to what their current evidence supports. I will critically present two arguments for the view. A common source of resistance to evidentialism is that there are intuitive cases where subjects should believe contrary to their evidence. I will present modest evidentialism as the view that subjects should believe in accord with what their evidence supports, but that this norm may be overridden under certain conditions. As such, a modest evidentialismaccommodates the intuitions behind a good deal of traditional anti-evidentialism.
193. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
W. Matthews Grant Scholastic Meditations: Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy Series, Vol. 44
194. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Books Received
195. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Jeanine M. Grenberg Kant and the Empiricists: Understanding Understanding
196. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Jens Timmermann Kant on Conscience, “Indirect” Duty, and Moral Error
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Kant’s concept of conscience has been largely neglected by scholars and contemporary moral philosophers alike, as has his concept of “indirect” duty. Admittedly, neither of them is foundational within his ethical theory, but a correct account of both in their own right and in combination can shed some new light on Kant’s moral philosophy as a whole. In this paper, I first examine a key passage in which Kant systematically discusses the role of conscience, then give a systematic account of “indirect” duties and the function of hypothetical imperatives in the course of their generation. I then turn to the possibility of moral error and the part “indirect” duty can play in its prevention. In conclusion, I try to show how clarifying the concept of “indirect” duty can help us to shed light on the nature of Kantian ethics as a whole.
197. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Fergus Kerr The Big Typescript TS 213: German-English Scholars’ Edition
198. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Firmin DeBranander Stoic Realpolitik
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Thanks to its doctrines of natural right and moral egalitarianism and to its prominent historical role in defying totalitarian government, Stoicism is often cited as a touchstone for liberal democracy. Less well known, however, is an alternate lineage, culminating in a Stoic Realpolitik that emerges in Justus Lipsius’s political writings. The foundation of this Realpolitik becomes increasingly clear in the progression of Stoic thought through Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius. Tracing this lineage reveals that the subject of politics isfundamentally problematic for Stoicism, especially since the denigration of politics is central to Stoic ethics. The Stoics ultimately arrive at a surprising moral pessimism, evidenced most prominently in Marcus’s Meditations. In Lipsius’s version of Stoic Realpolitik, the populace is characterized as being of inconstant behavior, and Stoicism is viewed as a resource for steeling the prince’s character against the masses, whose moral emendation is hopeless.
199. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
H. E. Baber Reflections on Meaning
200. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 46 > Issue: 3
Cathay Liu, Alan Nelson Descartes Reinvented