Displaying: 141-160 of 6126 documents

0.212 sec

141. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 3
T. A. Cavanaugh DER and Policy: The Recommendation of a Topic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
If viable, DER justifies certain individual acts that—by definition—have two effects. Presumably, it would in some fashion (at the very least, redundantly) justify policies concerning the very same acts. By contrast, acts that sometimes have a good effect and sometimes have a bad effect do not have the requisite two effects such that DER can justify them immediately. Yet, a policy concerning numerous such acts would have the requisite good and bad effects. For while any one such act would lack the relevant two effects, a series of such acts and a policy governing such a series would have them. This paper addresses DER’s justification of policies that apply to such acts. It shows that there are certain acts which DER mediately justifies by justifying policies (having the requisite two effects) concerning them. Thus, it recommends the larger topic of DER’s bearing on policy.
142. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Brian Besong Reappraising the Manual Tradition
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Following the Second Vatican Council, the predominant trend in Catholic moral theology has been decidedly antagonistic toward the tradition that dominated moral theology before the Council: namely, the use and formulation of ecclesiastically-approved “manuals” or “handbooks” of moral theology, the contents of which chiefly involved general precepts of morally good and bad behavior as well as the extension of those precepts to particular cases. In this paper, I will oppose the dominant anti-manual trend. More particularly, I will first sketch what I take to be the central aspects of the manual tradition. Second, I will provide several arguments in favor of this tradition. Last, I will raise and respond to objections to this tradition that feature prominently in the works of Pinckaers and Cessario.
143. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Paul A. Macdonald Jr. Hell, the Problem of Evil, and the Perfection of the Universe
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this article, I address the question why God would create a world with damned human beings in it when (presumably) he could create a better world without damned human beings. Specifically, I explain and defend what I call the “perfection of the universe argument.” According to this argument, which is Augustinian and Thomistic in origin, it is entirely and equally consistent with divine goodness for God to create a world with damned human beings in it or a damnation-free world so long as God ensures that each world is good as a whole. I then respond to two different objections to this argument. Finally, I show how the perfection of the universe argument leaves room for hoping that we live in a world in which no human being is damned and God affords every human being a life that is good as a whole.
144. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Ryan Thornton, OFM From Theology through Metaphysics to Logic: John Duns Scotus’s Account of the Trinity without the “Formal Distinction”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One of the conventions when it comes to discussing the thought of John Duns Scotus is that he postulated a “formal distinction” between the divine essence and the divine persons in the Trinity. This study challenges the truth of that convention in two ways. By analyzing parallel passages from the three primary works in which he discusses the Trinity (the Lectura, Ordinatio, and Reportatio), it makes apparent that Scotus does not propose the phrase “formal distinction” as part of his explanation for the Trinitarian formula. More centrally, though, this study shows how the Subtle Doctor develops his thought along a consistent line, from theology through metaphysics to logic, that has as its centerpiece an argument for production in the divine. This argument is the real story behind Scotus’s account of the Trinity, as his ultimate conclusion is that God, in order to be God, must be a Trinity.
145. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Stephen Napier The Justification of Killing and Psychological Accounts of the Person
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
One typical route to justify abortion rights is to argue that human fetuses and embryos are not persons—call this the no-person strategy. Arguments for this strategy aim to justify a psychological account of the person and this is done by appealing to various thought experiments, particularly brain-transplant experiments. I argue that both (i) a hylomorphic account of the person is consistent with the intuitions these experiments generate; and (ii) the hylomorphic account is compatible with persons coming into being prior to the exercise of a psychological power. Thesis (i) suggests that thought experiments are not exclusive motivations for a psychological account (i.e., the hylomorphic account can be true assuming everything we learn from the experiments). Thesis (ii) suggests that only one of the two theories justifies abortion-rights. It follows that the no-person justification for abortion rights is under-determining.
146. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Patricia Moya Cañas, Alejandro Miranda Montecinos First Practical and Speculative Principles in Thomas Aquinas: Common Elements and Differences
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A central thesis in the ethics and epistemology of St. Thomas Aquinas is that both speculative and practical reason proceed from first principles in their search for truth. According to Aquinas, the first principles of both orders are analogous and share common features. However, it is not always easy to understand the extent of this analogy. In this paper we intend to analyze two common properties of the first principles to show similarities and differences that exist in the way these analogous properties are verified in each order of principles. Firstly, we expound which characteristics correspond to the knowledge of both orders of principles. Secondly, we examine the idea that the knowledge of all the first principles comes from sense knowledge. Finally, we address the idea that all other knowledge, of both the speculative order and the practical order, depends on first principles.
147. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Joseph Suk-Hwan Dowd Aquinas on Demonic Obstinacy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
To defend the idea of everlasting punishment in hell, some philosophers of religion have suggested that hell’s punishment lasts forever because the damned continue to sin forever. This suggestion raises a further question: Why would a being keep sinning forever? In this paper, I examine Thomas Aquinas’s attempt to explain why demons keep sinning forever. According to Aquinas, demons cannot stop sinning because they cannot revise the judgment that caused them to sin. At the end of the paper, I argue that if we accept retributivism, then we have good reasons to think creatures such as Aquinas’s demons would deserve everlasting punishment.
148. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Charles F. Capps Formal and Material Cooperation with Evil
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The categories of formal and material cooperation with evil have shifted in meaning since they were employed by St. Alphonsus Liguori in the eighteenth century. I attempt to recover their original meanings by showing how Liguori’s choice of terms reflects a Thomist conception of human action. Relying on the work of Elizabeth Anscombe to elaborate that conception, I advance two theses about the distinction between formal and material cooperation with evil that I believe are not generally accepted, even among Catholic philosophers and theologians. The first concerns when acting intentionally under the description “doing what the other intends” constitutes formal cooperation with evil. The second concerns when material cooperation with evil is justified by the principle of double effect.
149. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Christopher Toner Eudaimonic Ethics: The Philosophy and Psychology of Living Well. By Lorraine Besser-Jones
150. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Timothy Pawl Aquinas’s Ontology of the Material World: Change, Hylomorphism, and Material Objects. By Jeffrey E. Brower
151. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Mathew Lu Action and Character According to Aristotle: The Logic of the Moral Life. By Kevin L. Flannery, SJ
152. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Paul Kucharski The Root of Friendship: Self-Love and Self-Governance in Aquinas. By Anthony T. Flood
153. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Christopher O. Blum Philosophy of Biology. By Peter Godfrey-Smith
154. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Anthony J. Lisska What Happened In and To Moral Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Philosophical Essays In Honor of Alasdair Macintyre. Edited by Fran O’Rourke
155. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Jorge J. E. Gracia Modern Challenges to Past Philosophy: Arguments and Responses. By Thomas D. Sullivan and Russell Pannier
156. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Robert E. Wood Hegel’s Naturalism: Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life. By Terry Pinkard
157. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
C. Jeffery Kinlaw Hegel’s Introduction to the System: Encyclopaedia Phenomenology and Psychology. By Robert E. Wood
158. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 89 > Issue: 4
Contents of Volume 89 (2015)
159. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 1
Chad Engelland Perceiving Other Animate Minds in Augustine
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper dispels the Cartesian reading of Augustine’s treatment of mind and other minds by examining key passages from De Trinitate and De Civitate Dei. While Augustine does vigorously argue that mind is indubitable and immaterial, he disavows the fundamental thesis of the dualistic tradition: the separation of invisible spirit and visible body. The immediate self-awareness of mind includes awareness of life: that is, of animating a body. Each of us animates his or her own body; seeing other animated bodies enables us to see other animating souls or minds. Augustine’s affirmation of animation lets us perceive that other minds are present, but Descartes’s denial of animation renders others ineluctably absent. Augustine’s soul is no ghost because his body is no machine.
160. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 90 > Issue: 1
John G. Brungardt Charles De Koninck and the Sapiential Character of Natural Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his early career, Charles De Koninck defended two theses: first, that natural philosophy (understood along Aristotelian-Thomistic lines) and the modern sciences are formally distinct; and second, that natural philosophy is a qualified form of wisdom with respect to those particular sciences. Later in his career, De Koninck changed his mind about the first thesis. Does this change of mind threaten the coherence of his second thesis? First, I explain De Koninck’s original position on the real distinction between natural philosophy and the sciences and his reasoning for why natural philosophy possesses a qualified sapiential office. Second, I consider De Koninck’s change of mind and defend the conclusion that, even if the modern sciences are a dialectical extension of natural philosophy, the latter is still wisdom in relation to the former. Finally, I discuss both examples of this sapiential function and its limitations.