Displaying: 121-140 of 1984 documents

0.529 sec

121. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Rachana Kamtekar The Soul’s (After-) Life
122. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Rachana Kamtekar Levels of Argument: A Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics
123. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
David Neal Greenwood Porphyry, Rome, and Support for Persecution
124. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Kaitlyn Creasy Plato and Nietzsche: Their Philosophical Art
125. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Joseph Suk-Hwan Dowd Mortal Imitations of Divine Life: The Nature of the Soul in Aristotle’s De Anima
126. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
J.H. Lesher Verbs for Knowing in Heraclitus’ Rebuke of Hesiod (DK 22B57)
127. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Sara Ahbel-Rappe L’aporie ou l’experience des limites de la pensée dans le Peri Archon de Damaskios
128. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Mitchell Miller What the Dialectician Discerns: A New Reading of Sophist 253d-e
129. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Gregory Kirk Self-Knowledge and Ignorance in Plato’s Charmides
130. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Chiara Robbiano Being is not an object: An interpretation of Parmenides’ fragment DK B2 and a reflection on assumptions
131. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Rhodes Pinto ‘All things are full of gods’: Souls and Gods in Thales
132. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Nathanael Stein Explanation and Hypothetical Necessity in Aristotle
133. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Eduardo Boechat Stoic Physics and the Aristotelianism of Posidonius
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In a famous passage of his Geography, Strabo comments about a supposed peculiarity in the natural philosophy of the Stoic philosopher Posidonius of Apamea: ‘For there is much enquiry into causes in him [Posidonius], that is, “Aristotelising”, a thing which our School [the Stoics] sheers off from because of the concealment of causes’ (Strabo ii 3.8 = T 85 E-K). Yet, although the affinities between Posidonius’ aetiological project and Peripatetic scientific quest seem clear enough, scholarship has not investigated so far whether Posidonius’ interest in meteorology entailed the adoption of changes in the orthodox Stoic physics. This is the ultimate purpose of this article. I aim to show that Posidonius incorporated important Peripatetic concepts into Stoic cosmology. The article is divided into two sections. The first section presents the analysis of recent scholarship regarding the core concepts of the physics of the Early Stoa. In the second one, I examine in detail four fragments of Posidonius (F 84/97a, F 93a, F 229, F 219 EK) and identify the consistent modifications that he adopted: a finitist cosmological model, absolute directions in space guiding elemental motion, active and passive elements bearing mutually contrasting qualities, and heat as the efficient cause of meteorological phenomena.
134. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Sebastian Gertz Knowledge, Intellect and Being in Damascius’ Doubts and Solutions Concerning First Principles
135. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi Harmonia, Melos, and Rhythmos: Aristotle on Musical Education
136. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Filip Radovic Aristotle on Prevision through Dreams
137. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Cristian Tolsa Ptolemy’s law court analogy and Alexandrian philosophy
138. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
From Plato to Platonism
139. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 37 > Issue: 1
Nicholas Baima Philosopher Rulers and False Beliefs
140. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 37 > Issue: 1
David Ebrey Socrates on Why We Should Inquire