Displaying: 121-140 of 1166 documents

0.133 sec

121. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
Robert N. Beck Technology and Idealism
122. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
Frederick Sontag The God of Revolution
123. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 2
George J. Seidel Creativity In the Aesthetics of Schelling
124. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Stephen A. Erickson Cassirer’s Dialectic: A Critical Discussion
125. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Warren E. Steinkraus Annual Survey of Literature
126. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Richard T. Allen Self-Realization, Religion and Contradiction In Ethical Studies
127. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
H. D. Lewis Realism and Metaphysics
128. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Rex Martin Collingwood’s Essay on Philosophical Method
129. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
George J. Stack Husserl’s Concept of Persons
130. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Annika Thiem Specters of Sin and Salvation: Hermann Cohen, Original Sin, and Rethinking the Critique of Religion
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article examines the relationship between theology and ethics through the critique of original sin that the German-Jewish thinker Hermann Cohen advances. The concept of original sin has tacit normative consequences through conceiving the human condition as constitutively imperfect and prone to moral evil. Cohen criticizes the consequent theological ethics that privileges salvation from this world over justice in this world. Through Cohen this article argues that rather than focusing on explicitly normative precepts, a critical account of the relationship between theology and ethics needs to examine how theologicalconcepts shape ethical affects and commitments.
131. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Jennifer Mensch Orcid-ID Material Unity and Natural Organism in Locke
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines one of the central complaints regarding Locke’s Essay, namely, its supposed incoherence. The question is whether Locke can successfully maintain a materialistic conception of matter, while advancing a theory of knowledge that will constrain the possibilities for a cognitive accessto matter from the start. In approaching this question I concentrate on Locke’s account of unity. While material unity can be described in relation to Locke’s account of substance, real essence, and nominal essence, a separate discussion will be called for altogether in the case of organic unity. In closing, I turn to Kant as a model for locating Locke’s purported incoherence, suggesting that his “skeptical idealism” yields the same epistemic advantages as those won by Kant’s “empirical realism.”
132. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Wong Kwok Kui Schelling’s Criticism of Kant’s Theory of Time
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper aims at engaging Kant’s and Schelling’s theories of time in dialogue. It begins with Schelling’s famous criticism of Kant’s theory of time in his Weltalter (Ages of the World). It will examine this question from four main perspectives, namely the unity of time; time and a unitary object of experience;subjectivity of time; and the problem of infinity of time. It will show that Schelling’s criticism may instigate some fundamental reflections on Kant’s theory oftime, the relation between objective and subjective time, and the possibilities of connecting Kant’s different meanings of time in his first Critique. Further, it willshow that despite the fundamental differences between Kant’s and Schelling’s philosophical systems, some of Schelling’s ideas about time may have their earlier expressions in Kant. While Schelling has gone further and radicalized some insights from Kant in his own version of idealism, his criticism of Kant may find possible responses from the latter’s first Critique.
133. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Edward Eugene Kleist Schopenhauer on the Individuation and Teleology of Intelligible Character
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A problem arises in Schopenhauer’s claim that each individual person’s will, or intelligible character, is timeless. The principium individuationis depends upon spatio-temporal determinations governing the world as representation. As individual, one’s individual character would seem to depend upon spatio-temporalconditions. Yet, Schopenhauer adopts the Kantian distinction between empirical character and intelligible character, with the individual’s intelligible characterremaining the timeless Ding-an-sich, or will. In response to this problem, I proceed in four stages. First, I examine why Schopenhauer appropriated the Kantiandistinction between intelligible and empirical character. Secondly, I argue in favor of the solution which indicates that, for Schopenhauer, each individual’s intelligible character is related to the Platonic Idea unique to that individual. In the third stage, I determine how the teleological claims in Schopenhauer’s doctrineof Ideas bear on the problem. In the fourth stage, I suggest how Schopenhauer’s account presents a phenomenology of the unity of consciousness.
134. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Nicholas Rescher Mind and Matter: An Ancient Problem Reconsidered
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The ancient problem of mind-matter relationship still has traction. Cartesian dualism created a seemingly impossible divide here. But with the decline of mechanism on the matter sides the issue of trans-categorical causality no larger secured insurmountable. However, with a more open concept of causality in view, there is no reason to think that the causality at issue here is a one way street from matter to mind. The mind-brain can be seen as a unified hermeneutical engine that permits of two-way operation. Mark Twain asked “When the body is drunk, does the mind stay sober?” But one may just as well ask “When the mind says ‘Write!,’ does the hand remain immobile?”
135. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Marco Segala Schopenhauer and the Empirical Confirmations of Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper focuses on Schopenhauer’s On the Will in Nature (1836), a book which is generally underestimated by scholars interested in Schopenhauer’sphilosophy. This essay analyses its genesis in Schopenhauer’s manuscripts, examines its role in Schopenhauer’s thought and its relationship with The World asWill and Representation, and locates its content and meaning with reference to the philosophical and scientific context. Aim of the article is a better understanding of Schopenhauer’s treatise, and such a scope is pursued by accurate insight of its central theme: the notion of Bestätigung, that is the scientific corroboration of the philosophical knowledge.
136. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Eric Entrican Wilson On the Nature of Judgment in Kant’s Transcendental Logic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This essay explores Kant’s account of judging. In it, I argue for two central claims. First, Kant defines the act of judgment as the exercise of a particular type of authority (Befugnis). When a person makes a judgment, she makes a claim to speak for everyone, and not just herself. She puts something forward as true. Kant’s term for this discursive authority is “objectivity validity,” and he identifies this as the essential feature of judging. Second, the Categories and the Principles are what authorize a person to put something forward as true. This means that the objective validity of a judgment is supplied by the rules of the understanding rather than by something outside the mind.
137. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Gerard Kuperus The Development of the Role of the Spectator in Kant’s Thinking: The Evolution of the Copernican Revolution
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I discuss the development of Kant’s Critical project in the pre-critical writings. I am particularly focusing upon the problems that Kant encounters in developing the idea of a transcendental subject. This helps us to understand the radical nature of Kant’s project in which he does not merely turn around the relationship between subject and object, but also has to redefine the nature of the subject. The development of the subject starts with Kant’s idea of an observer who actively determines qualities in the object (instead of passively taking it in). Ultimately the spectator becomes a subject that is constituted a priori, independent of experience. In order to arrive at this idea of a subject, Kant needs to overcome the tradition that in many ways still determines his thinking.
138. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Jason J. Howard Schelling and Paleolithic Cave Painting: On the Appeal of Aesthetic Experience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
My article utilizes the insights of F. W. J. Schelling’s work on aesthetics to explain the unique appeal of cave painting for people of the Upper Paleolithic,focusing mostly on the caves of Chauvet and Lascaux. Schelling argues that the unique value of artistic practices comes in the way they reconcile agents withtheir deepest ontological contradictions, namely, the tension between biological necessity and human freedom. I argue that the cave paintings of Chauvet andLascaux fit well with Schelling’s approach and his insight that art seeks to reveal the contradictory capacities of self-conscious beings in a state of fundamentalattunement rather than in discordance and disharmony. My contention is that in taking this approach, whereby aesthetic practices engender an intuition of theabsolute identity between nature and mind, we can better explain why the practice of cave painting endured for over twenty-thousand years as one common styleof artistic practice.
139. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
Scott Stapleford A Refutation of Idealism from 1777
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The paper identifies a possible precedent for Kant’s Refutation of Idealism in the work of Johann Nicolaus Tetens. An attempt is made to reconstruct the reasoning that led Tetens to reject idealism as a false starting point, and some parallels are drawn between Tetens’s psychologistic approach to the problem andKant’s transcendental methodology.
140. Idealistic Studies: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1/2
William R. Woodward Hermann Lotze’s Gestalt Metaphysics in Light of the Schelling and Hegel Renaissance (1838–1841)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Situating Lotze in the School of Speculative Theology, I use debates about Schelling’s critique of Hegel—then and now—to understand Lotze’s critique of Hegel. Lotze’s early metaphysics seems to employ a version of Hegel’s dialectical analysis of being, phenomena, and mind emphasizing “the interconnection of things.” One can equally argue that he proceeds in an analytic style of reviewing and testing alternative theories. My tentative conclusion is that he assumes the existence of reality (the Absolute) like Schelling, and makes cognition a process subordinate to that reality. In this respect, he goes beyond his Kantian mentors J. F. Fries and E. F. Apelt. From all these sources came a radically original Gestalt metaphysics. For example, he reverses Kant’s forms of intuition (Anschauung) into “forms of intuitability”(Anschaulichkeit), including the relational categories of space, time, motion, mechanism, organism, law, and event. He then makes the categories into ethical levels of a “teleological idealism.” In this way he overcomes his Herbartian teachers’ separation of metaphysics from ethics, evincing his center Hegelian roots.