Displaying: 1-20 of 240414 documents

0.78 sec

1. Philosophy Today: Volume > 63 > Issue: 1
Catherine Homan The Play of Being and Nothing: World, Earth, and Cosmos in Eugen Fink
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The question permeating much of Eugen Fink’s work is whether a nonmetaphysical thinking of the world is possible. Fink views metaphysics as understanding the world merely from the side of beings and as a container of things. A nonmetaphysical thinking would be cosmological; it would think the world as a totality, as the origin of being, of beings, of time, and of space. This thinking requires a radical way of thinking that which cannot be thought: the nothing that allows being and beings to come to appearance at all. My analysis aims to articulate more clearly what Fink means by thinking cosmologically by tracing his understanding of world, earth, and cosmos and the interplay of being and nothing at stake in each. I clarify how Fink both inherits and goes beyond the philosophies of Kant, Husserl, and Heidegger to provide a way of thinking through that which resists articulation.
... the early Greeks recognized a difference between being and beings, a difference ... of the idea of being” (cited in Bruzina 1995: liii). Since space and time are a ... The question permeating much of Eugen Fink’s work is whether a nonmetaphysical ...
2. Semiotics: 1994
Benjamin E. Mayer Metaphysics: Permanently to be Exceeded, Permanently to Endure
... of the privilege of presence, so too there is a moment—and ... to the modes of time, the past and the future. Being is nontime ... . Thus, the question of the relation between 'metaphysics' and ...
3. The Philosophical Review: Volume > 113 > Issue: 2
Daniel Sutherland Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics and the Greek Mathematical Tradition
... as there is no sense that can be given to the ratio between an area and a volume ... distinguishes between two sorts of magnitude, quanta and quantitas; the former is a concrete ... regarded as a genus, then it is a lowest species [species infimae]and the difference of ...
4. Southwestern Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 10 > Issue: 2
David B. Cornay Kant and the Closure of the Epoch of the Metaphysics of Presence
... transition of a now which is between the nonbeing of a not yet and of a no more. It is ... " (see KdrV A. 598-B. 626). Given the difference of thought and intuition, that ... distinction between the concept of a thing in itself and that of appearance is not ...
5. Philosophy Today: Volume > 51 > Issue: Supplement
Emanuela Bianchi Aristotelian Dunamis and Sexual Difference: An Analysis of Adunamia and Dunamis Meta Logou in Metaphysics Theta
... sexual difference, the female is a sort of deformed or mutilated ... of privation—the first distinction he gives is between a simple ... says is that the contrary isthereand manifest in a peculiar ...
6. Heidegger Circle Proceedings: Volume > 15
Joseph J. Kockelmans On the Function of the Ontological Difference in Heidegger's Transcendental Ontology
... is taken in the context of investigations which have a transcendental and ... problematic as we find it in Being and Time and Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics ... that Being is to be interpreted from the perspective of time and that this ...
7. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 26 > Issue: 2
George J. Seidel Heidegger and the Overcoming of Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Heidegger revisits German idealism after the “turn” in his thought in the mid-1930’s. There are a couple of reasons for this. One is philosophical, if not “theological” in his sense of that term. The other is personal. This later reason is emphasized by Otto Pöggeler, who suggests that after 1945 Heidegger sought to understand what had gone wrong in the tragic European debacle. Heidegger will lay the blame at the doorstep of what he terms onto-theology and the subjectivism he sees as endemic to the German idealist tradition, above all as exemplified in Hegel’s “onto-theo-ego-logy.” The article explores Heidegger’s reading of this tradi­tion of German philosophy as it begins with Leibniz and culminates in Nietzsche. It is the Event itself that makes possible the overcoming of metaphysics and its onto-theology. As Heidegger says in Contributions to Philosophy (From the Event), the ens realissimum (das Seiendste) “is” no more. It is the Event (Ereignis) that is the “most real,” since it is the Event that shows up and manifests itself as the revelation of the truth of Beinge in Da-sein, the being that is there in the Event.
... same time. There is The Metaphysics of German Idealism (1991), lectures ... metaphysics, announced in Being and Time, is really a return to the origin ... 2009b, 102–3). 17 The metaphysics of Hegel, according to Heidegger, is a mix ...
8. Process Studies: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Juliana Geran Pilon Becoming: A Problem for Determinists?
...'s metaphysics of time entaiIs (1). Now Iet us b,egin frorn the other end and examine the ... ,roperty and if the future is detenninate, there is no difference between a future ... sibilities. A detelminist oould agree here and still hold that there is a difference b'etween ...
9. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Anna Marmodoro Aristotle on Complex Perceptual Content. The Metaphysics of the Common Sense
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his theory of perception Aristotle is committed to the principle that there is a one-to-one correspondence between a sensible quality, the modification of a sense organ by that quality, and the content of the perceptual experience of it. But on the basis of this principle, simultaneous perceptions of different sensible qualities give rise only to distinct perceptual contents. This generates the problem of how we become aware of complex perceptual content, e.g. in discerning red from cold. This paper examines the alternative (although not equally explanatorily powerful) models that Aristotle offers in the De Anima and in his biological works to account for complex perceptual content.
...: The object of sight is the visible, and what is visible is (a) colour and (b ... is a one-to-one correspondence between a sensible quality, the modification of a ... modification of the appropriate special sense organ by the form.^ There is a one ...
10. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 1
Sylvia Carli Energeia and Being-in-Time
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Aristotle defines time as “the number of movement (kinēsis) with respect to before and after” (Physics 4.11.219b2). The relation between sublunar substances, which have within themselves a principle of movement and rest, and time, therefore, appears unproblematic. Sensible substances, however, also perform perfect activities (energeiai) and, in the passages in which he most clearly outlines the nature of such activities, the philosopher leaves the issue of their temporality unresolved. As a result, scholars have speculated about different ways of understanding it. This paper argues that the Aristotelian corpus does offer precise indications on this issue. The Physics distinguishes between two modalities of being in time, namely, being-in-time in virtue of one’s nature and being-in-time accidentally. The case is made that energeiai belong to the class of things that are in time accidentally and that this way of understanding their relation to time fits their distinctive nature and is faithful to the phenomena.
... number, or (2b) that there is a number of it.” 42 The first sense ... that there is no difference between the two kinds of processes ... in virtue of one’s nature and being-in-time accidentally. The case is made that ...
11. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 45 > Issue: 2
Oliva Blanchette Are There Two Questions of Being?
... are there two names (244b)? Being is posited as in the soul, a kind of third in ... , caught up in what remains for us the question of metaphysics. It is time perhaps to ... of being as being and one of be as be, and has the difference between them, or ...
12. Studia Phaenomenologica: Volume > 20
Paul Slama The Onto-Agathological Fold of Metaphysics: Aristotle, Plato and Heidegger
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The goal of this paper is twofold. First, it aims to identify in Heidegger’s work a determination of the history of metaphysics parallel to the famous onto-theological one, and which I will label onto-agathological. Based upon a text from the course of 1935, “Einführung in die Metaphysik,” I argue that for Heidegger the history of metaphysics is not only the Aristotelian onto-theology, but is also characterized by the Platonic pre-eminence of the good over being (Republic 509c). In short, it is an onto-agathological history. Second, and as a consequence of the first point, I will flesh out the hypothesis of another history metaphysics, and emphasize its strong phenomenological content which stands in opposition to the Neo-Kantianism of Windelband and Rickert.
... it is necessary to think of a profound kinship and at the same time a difference ... difference between ontology and theology, there is the proximity that unites two ... , it is an onto-agathological history. Second, and as a consequence of the first ...
13. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
J. Colin McQuillan A Merely Logical Distinction: Kant's Objection to Leibniz and Wolff
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Throughout his career, Immanuel Kant objects that Leibniz and Wolff make the distinction between sensible and intellectual cognition into a “merely logical” distinction. Although it is not clear that anyone in the Leibnizian-Wolffian tradition actually holds this view, Kant’s objection helps to define the “real” distinction between sensible and intellectual cognition that he defends in his inaugural dissertation in 1770. Kant raises the same objection against Leibniz and Wolff in the Critique of Pure Reason, but replaces the “real” distinction he defends in his inaugural dissertation with a new “transcendental” distinction between intuitions and concepts. This paper examines Kant’s objection to Leibniz and Wolff and the different alternatives he proposes, in order to highlight an important element in the development of his critical philosophy.
... and logic. 42 Because there is a science of the distinct cognition of the higher ... which belongs to the understanding as that of which there is a ... him to highlight the difference between the origin and content of sensible and ...
14. Journal of Philosophical Research: Volume > 18
Michael R. Baumer Chasing Aristotle’s Categories Down the Tree of Grammar
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper addresses the problem of the origin and principle of Aristotle’s distinctions among the categories. It explores the possibilities of reformulating and reviving the “grammatical” theory, generally ascribed first to Trendelenburg. The paper brings two new perspectives to the grammatical theory: that of Aristotle’s own theory of syntax and that of contemporary linguistic syntax and semantics. I put forth a provisional theory of Aristotle’s categories in which (1) I propose that the Categories sets forth a theory of lexical structure, with the ten categories emerging as lexical or semantic categories, and (2) I suggest conceptual links, both in Aristotle’s writings and in actuality, between these semantic categories and certain grammatical inflections.
... the theory of categories there is a correlation set up between the structures of ... context in which there is a small and definite list of the way something can be ... (225a34–226b1). The analysis of unity analogously concludes that there must be as ...
15. Heidegger Circle Proceedings: Volume > 18
Kenneth Maly The Transformation of "Logic" in Heraclitus: Heidegger's 1944 Lecture Course: Logik: Heraklits Lehre vom Logos
... Wesepsherkunft). seeing is in a way Greek and at the same time, in ... ; it is the activity of ratio and is therefore a transaction of ... a "disclosure" and is the equi-valent of ,{f v1 : a bringing ...
16. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 15 > Issue: 2
Jeffrey D. Gower The King of the Cosmos: Potentiality, Actuality, and the Logic of Sovereignty in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Λ
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper offers a deconstructive reading of the pure actuality of the un­moved mover of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Aristotle describes this first, unmoved principle of movement as a divine sovereign—the king of the cosmos—and maintains that the good governance of the cosmos depends on its unmitigated unity and pure actuality. It is striking, then, when Giorgio Agamben claims that Aristotle bequeathed the paradigm of sovereignty to Western philosophy not through his arguments for the pure actuality of the unmoved mover but rather through his description of the essence of potentiality. An interpretation of Aristotle’s account of potentiality in Metaphysics Theta therefore prepares the way for a deconstruction of the unity and pure actuality of the divine sovereign. I argue that the repetition of nous in Aristotle’s description of the divine thinking of thinking betrays traces of division and difference at the heart of divine sovereignty. If this is the case, then actuality and potentiality become indis­cernible at the level of the absolute and the sovereign corresponds to the bifurcated site of this indiscernibility.
...—covers over a difference between the activity of divine thinking and its ... Metaphysics Theta therefore prepares the way for a deconstruction of the unity and pure ... , “The rule of many is not good; let there be one ruler” (1076a4). 2 The quotation ...
17. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Thomas V. Upton Aristotle on Hypothesis and the Unhypothesized First Principle
... mind at Metaphysics IV, 3, and Ross takes hypothesis to be a hybrid between what is ... ὑποθέσεως συλλογισμοὺς), and that there is the possibility of demonstrating or defining ... than (b) (Kirwan) or a hybrid of (a) and (c) (Ross). And because of the use of his ...
18. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 81 > Issue: 4
Adrian Pabst The Primacy of Relation over Substance and the Recovery of a Theological Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This essay concerns the problem of individuation in metaphysics in relation to the question of individuality in politics. It rejects the assumption in muchof ancient, modern, and contemporary philosophy and theology that unity and diversity are opposed and that this opposition produces conflict and violence. Theproposed alternative is a metaphysics and politics of relationality. This alternative is not so much indebted to Aristotle, but instead goes back to Platonist metaphysics and its transformation by Augustine and Boethius. By privileging substance over all other categories, Aristotle not only relegated the transcendent immaterial actuality from the immanence of the material world but also divorced particular beings from the universal Prime Mover or God. By contrast, for Plato, the transcendent universal Good individuates all immanent particulars relationally at the level of the oikos, the polis, and the cosmos. Crucially, by combining the concept of creation ex nihilo with the metaphysics of participation, Augustine and Boethius reconfi gured Plato’s Good in the direction of the Creator-God and Trinitarian relationality. Thus, each and every being is individuated because it is a particular reflection of the universal Good, a unique and singular expression of God’s self-communicative actualization in the world.
... alternative is a metaphysics and politics of relationality. This alternative is not so ... proposed alternative is a metaphysics and politics of relationality. This alternative ... and every being is individuated because it is a particular reflection of the ...
19. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 41 > Issue: 3
Stephen Watson Heidegger, Rationality, and the Critique of Judgment
.... On the one hand, there is a return to the realm of the "pre-reflective" and to ... of the Übergänge at work in the difference between Being and beings, what then is ... project of that volume:In Being and Time, the term "hermeneutics" is used in a still ...
20. Forum Philosophicum: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
George J. Seidel The Imagination in Kant and Fichte, and Some Reflections on Heidegger’s Interpretation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The paper deals with the meaning of the transcendental imagination in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, comparing it with the productive imagination proposed by Fichte in his Wissenschaftslehre of 1794. It also presents Heidegger’s views concerning both Kant and Fichte. Regarding Kant there is also a discussion of the difference between the first and second editions of the First Critique. It may be noted that Heidegger prefers the first edition to the second, since, in his view, the latter leads into German Idealism. In Fichte’s philosophy the imagination plays a considerably larger role than it does in Kant. And Heidegger early on (in 1929) recognizes the importance of Fichte as a philosopher in its own right, and not just, as was customary in the period, a mere transitional figure between Kant and Hegel. The paper concludes with a critique of Heidegger’s views regarding both Fichte and Kant. Though there is an addendum discussing the function of the imagination in the aesthetics of Kant (classicism), in that of Fichte (romanticism), and a brief comparison with Heidegger’s own aesthetics.
... concerning both Kant and Fichte. Regarding Kant there is also a discussion of the ... a discussion of the difference between the first and second editions of the ... a difference between Kant’s Gegenstand and Heidegger’s Sein, so is there a ...