Displaying: 1-20 of 1137 documents

0.291 sec

1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 4
Ian T. E. Boyd The Problem of Self-Destroying Sin in John Milton’s Samson Agonistes
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper, I argue that John Milton, in his tragedy Smason Agonistes, raises and offers a solution to a version of the problem of evil raised by Marilyn McCord Adams. Sections I and II are devoted to the presentation of Adams’s version of the problem and its place in the current discussion of the problem of evil. In section III, I present Milton’s version of the problem as it is raised in Samson Agonistes. The solution Milton offers to this problem is taken up in section IV and examined in section V. Last, in section VI, I explore briefly the existential aspect of Milton’s solution.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 4
Nicholas Wolterstorff Barth on Evil
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I offer an interpretation of Karl Barth’s discussion of evil in volume III/3 of his Church Dogmatics. It is, I contend, an extraordinarily rich, imaginative and provocative discussion, philosophically informed, yet very different from the mainline philosophical treatments of the topic---and from the mainline theological treatments as well. I argue that though Barth’s account is certainly subject to critique at various points, especially on ontological matters, nonetheless philosophers are well advised to take seriously what he says. It offers a powerful attack on many standard lines of thought.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 4
Derk Pereboom Kant on God, Evil, and Teleology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his mature period Kant maintained that human beings have never devised a theory that shows how the existence of God is compatible with the evil that actually exists. But he also held that an argument could be developed that we human beings might well not have the cognitive capacity to understand the relation between God and the world, and that therefore the existence of God might nevertheless be compatible with the evil that exists. At the core of Kant’s position lies the claim that God’s relation to the world might well not be purposive in the way we humans can genuinely understand such a relation. His strategy involves demonstrating that the teleological argument is unsound - for this argument would establish that the relation between God and the world is purposive in a way we can grasp - and showing that by way of a Spinozan conception we can catch an intellectual glimpse of an alternative picture of the relation between God and the world.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 4
Jerry L. Walls “As the Waters Cover the Sea”: John Wesley on the Problem of Evil
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
John Wesley explained the existence of evil in moral rather than metaphysical terms. His understanding of the fall was fairly typical of western theology and he also enthusiastically embraced a version of the felix culpa theme as essential for theodicy. Unlike many influential western theologians, he also relied heavily on libertarian freedom to account for evil. His most striking proposal for theodicy involves his eschatalogical vision of the future in which he believed the entire world living then will be converted. I argue that his theodicy is implicitly universalist, especially in its eschatalogical speculations, and show that this is in tension with his strong libertariancommitments.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
James K. A. Smith The Art of Christian Atheism: Faith and Philosophy in Early Heidegger
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his early work, Martin Heidegger argues for a rigorous methodological atheism in philosophy, which is not opposed to religious faith but only to the impact of faith when one is philosophizing. For the young Heidegger, the philosopher, even though possibly a religious person, must be an atheist when doing philosophy. Christian philosophy, then, is a round square. In this essay, I unpack Heidegger’s methodological considerations and attempt to draw parallels with other traditions which argue for the possibility of a Christian philosophy but at root concede Heidegger’s atheism. In conclusion, I propose that it is precisely Heidegger’s work which points to the inescapabiIity of and opens the door to religious philosophy.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Lynn D. Cates Berkeley on the Work of the Six Days
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In the Three Dialogues, Hylas challenges Philonous to give a plausible account of the mosaic account of creation in subjective idealistic terms. Strangely, when faced with two alternative strategies, Berkeley chooses the less viable option and explicates the mosaic account of creation in terms of perceptibility. I shall show that Berkeley’s account of creation trivializes the affair, if it does not fail outright.
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Richard Cross Duns Scotus on Eternity and Timelessness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Scotus consistently holds that eternity is to be understood as timelessness. In his early Lectura, he criticizes Aquinas’ account of eternity on the grounds that (1) it entails collapsing past and future into the present, and (2) it entails a B-theory of time, according to which past, present and future are all ontologically on a par with each other. Scotus later comes to accept something like Aquinas’ account of God’s timelessness and the B-theory of time which it entails. Scotus also offers a refutation of his earlier argument that Aquinas’ account of eternity entails collapsing past and future into the present.
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
John Sanders Why Simple Foreknowledge Offers No More Providential Control Than the Openness of God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines the question of whether the theory of simply foreknowledge (SF) provides God with greater providential control than does the theory of present knowledge (PK). It is claimed by the proponents of SF that a deity lacking such knowledge would not be able to provide the sort of providential aid commonly thought by theists to be given by God. To see whether this is the case I first distinguish two different versions of how God’s foreknowledge is accessed according to simple foreknowledge. These two versions are then utilized to examine seven different areas of divine providence to assess the utility of simple foreknowledge. I conclude that SF affords no greater providential control than PK.
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Steven D. Crain Divine Action in a World Chaos: An Evaluation of John Polkinghorne’s Model of Special Divine Action
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
John Polkinghorne, formerly a physicist and now an Anglican priest and theologian, has made a significant contribution to the current dialogue between Christian theology and the natural sciences. I examine here his reflection on what is commonly called the problem of special divine action in the world. Polkinghorne argues that God acts in the world via a “topdown” or “downward” mode of causation that exploits the indeterministic openness of chaotic systems without requiring that God violate natural laws. In response, I argue: (1) that divine intervention in response to human sin is theologically, as well as scientifically unobjectionable; and (2) that the belief that God is the transcendent creator of the world renders the “causal joint” between God and the world metaphysical in nature, thus obviating the need to uncover a physical feature of the world that God exploits in order to act in the world.
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Gordon Knight Universalism and the Greater Good: A Response to Talbott
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Thomas Talbott has recently argued in this journal that the three propositions 1) God wills universal salvation 2) God has the power to produce universal salvation and 3) some persons are not saved are inconsistent. I contend that this claim is only true if God has no overriding purposes that would place restrictions on the means God uses to achieve God’s ends. One possible example of such an overriding purpose would be God’s aim to produce the most good. I end by suggesting that while God’s purpose of universal salvation does render the achievement of this end probable, it is by no means necessary.
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
E. Feser Has Trinitarianism Been Shown to Be Coherent?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Macnamara, La Palme Reyes, and Reyes have recently claimed to have shown decisively that the doctrine of the Trinity is internally consistent. They claim, furthermore, that their account does not commit them to any exotic emendations of standard logical theory. The paper demonstrates that they have established neither of these claims. In particular, it is argued that the set of statements they show to be consistent in fact expresses Sabellianism, not Trinitarianism; and that they can avoid this result only via commitment to the (questionable) doctrine of relative identity.
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Bernard D. Katz, Elmar J. Kremer The Cosmological Argument Without the Principle of Sufficient Reason
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
We formulate a version of the Cosmological Argument that deploys an epistemic principle of explanation in place of the traditional Principle of Sufficient Reason. The epistemic principle asserts that if there is a possible explanation of a fact, and some proposition is entailed by that explanation and by every other possible explanation of that fact, it is reasonable to accept that proposition. We try to show that there is a possible explanation of the fact that there are contingent beings and that any possible explanation of this fact presupposes that there is a necessary being. We conclude that it is reasonable to believe that there is a necessary being.
13. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Daniel Howard-Snyder In Defense of Naïve Universalism
14. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Katherin A. Rogers Does God Cause Sin?: Anselm of Canterbury Versus Jonathan Edwards on Human Freedom and Divine Sovereignty
15. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Michael J. Murray Natural Providence (Or Design Trouble)
16. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Merold Westphal The God Who Will Be: Hermeneutics and the God of Promise
17. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Hugo A. Meynell The Philosophy of Dooyeweerd: A Transcendental Thomist Appraisal
18. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
J. William Forgie The Alleged Dependency of the Cosmological Argument on the Ontological
19. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Wes Morriston Must Metaphysical Time Have a Beginning?
20. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 4
Lynne Rudder Baker WHY CHRISTIANS SHOULD NOT BE LIBERTARIANS: AN AUGUSTINIAN CHALLENGE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The prevailing view of Christian philosophers today seems to be that Christianity requires a libertarian conception of free will. Focusing on Augustine’s mature anti-Pelagian works, I try to show that the prevailing view is in error. Specifically, I want to show that---on Augustine’s view of grace-a libertarian account of free will is irrelevant to salvation. On Augustine’s view, the grace of God through Christ is sufficient as weIl as necessary for salvation. Salvation is entirely in the hands of God, totally independent of anything that any human being might do. And faith, the human response to salvation, is best understood in terms of a compatibilist account of freedom.