Displaying: 1-15 of 15 documents

0.194 sec

1. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 27 > Issue: 2
Anna L. Peterson Environmental Ethics, Ecological Theology, and Natural Selection
... Darwinism,” eugenics, even genocide, as Peter Singer, E. O. Wilson, Richard ... Dawkins, and others have discovered. Intellectually, however, it is not clear ...
2. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 4
David K. Goodin Living with Ambiguity: Religious Naturalism and the Menace of Evil
... Richard Dawkins and Christopher Hitchens fans. Crosby’s arguments are ...
3. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 33 > Issue: 3
Eric Katz Dark Green Religion: Nature Spirituality and the Planetary Future
... consciousness as a form of religion from Richard Dawkins, but then proceeds to ...
4. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 17 > Issue: 4
Nicholas Agar Valuing Species and Valuing Individuals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
My goal in this paper is to account for the value of species in terms of the value of individual organisms that make them up. Many authors have pointed to an apparent conflict between a species preservationist ethic and moral theories that place value on individuals. I argue for an account of the worth of individual organisms grounded in the representational goals of those organisms. I claim thatthis account leads to an acceptably extensive species preservationist ethic.
.... Williams, Richard Dawkins, and others, natural selection, the principle organizing ... , 1966) and Richard Dawkins, The Extended Phenotype (Oxford: Oxford University Press ... VALUING INDIVIDUALS 35 See Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford: Oxford ...
5. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 10 > Issue: 3
Thomas W. Simon Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin: The Dialectical Biologist
... only unit of selection. Vulgar Darwinists such as Richard Dawkins in The Selfish ...
6. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 14 > Issue: 2
Lawrence E. Johnson Toward the Moral Considerability of Species and Ecosystems
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I develop the thesis that species and ecosystems are living entities with morally significant interests in their own right and defend it against leading objections. Contrary to certain claims, it is possible to individuate such entities sufficiently well. Indeed, there is a sense in which such entities define their own nature. I also consider and reject the argument that species and ecosystems cannot have interests or even traits in their own right because evolution does not proceed on that level. Although evolution proceeds on the level of the genotype, those selected are able to cooperate in entities of various higher orders—including species and ecosystems. Having their own nature and interests, species and ecosystems can meaningfully be said to have moral standing.
... difficulty is summarized as follows by Richard Dawkins, a gradualist who denies ... 3 Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker (Harlow. England: Longmans, 1986), p ...
7. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 15 > Issue: 1
Peter S. Wenz Minimal, Moderate, and Extreme Moral Pluralism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Concentrating on the views of Christopher Stone, who advocates moral pluralism, and J. Baird Callicott, who criticizes Stone’s views, I argue that the debate has been confused by a conflation of three different positions, here called minimal, moderate, and extreme moral pluralism. Minimal pluralism is uncontroversial because all known moral theories are minimally pluralistic. Extreme pluralism is defective in the ways that Callicott alleges and, moreover, is inconsistent with integrity in the moral life. However, moderate pluralism of the sort that I advance in Environmental Justice is distinct from extreme pluralism and free of its defects. It is also consistent with Callicott’s version of Aldo Leopold’s land ethic, which is itself moderately pluralistic.
... thinking. In the hands of Richard Dawkins, the driving force behind evolution is ... social conduct.”23 In his book, he 18 Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (New York ...
8. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 34 > Issue: 3
Neil A. Manson Anthropocentrism, Exoplanets, and the Cosmic Perspective
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Nonanthropocentric environmental philosophy is a response to two kinds of anthropocentrism: personal anthropocentrism, according to which being human involves the possession of some or all of a set of properties typical of persons, and biological anthropocentrism, according to which being a human involves being a member of the species Homo sapiens. Nonanthropocentric environmental philosophy itself becomes problematic when it is viewed in terms of two arguments that it often seems to imply: the “Planetary Perspective Argument,” which rejects both forms of anthropocentrism and seeks to maximize good outcomes and minimize bad outcomes in terms of life’s point of view, the land’s point of view, or the global ecosystem’s point of view, and the “Cosmic Perspective Argument,” which is structurally analagous to the planetary perspective argument but has much more sweeping empirical premises driven by recent work in cosmology, astrobiology, and exoplanet science. The ultimate problem for environmental philosophers is to find a way to remain nonanthropocentric without succumbing to the indifference of the cosmic perspective.
... 19 Indeed, biologist Richard Dawkins suggests that the correct ... , but among genes. See Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford ...
9. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 10 > Issue: 3
Harley Cahen Against the Moral Considerability of Ecosystems
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Are ecosystems morally considerable-that is, do we owe it to them to protect their “interests”? Many environmental ethicists, impressed by the way that individual nonsentient organisms such as plants tenaciously pursue their own biological goals, have concluded that we should extend moral considerability far enough to include such organisms. There is a pitfall in the ecosystem-to-organism analogy, however. We must distinguish a system’s genuine goals from the incidental effects, or byproducts, of the behavior of that system’s parts. Goals seem capable of giving rise to interests; byproducts do not. It is hard to see how whole ecosystems can be genuinely goal-directed unless group selection occurs at the community level. Currently, mainstream ecological and evolutionary theory is individualistic. From such a theory it follows that the apparent goals of ecosystems are mere byproducts and, as such, cannot ground moral considerability.
10. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 9 > Issue: 1
Steven E. Edwards In Defense of Environmental Economics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The appropriateness of economic valuations of the natural environment is defended on the basis of an objective analysis of individuals’ preferences. The egoistic model of “economic man” substantiates economic valuations of instrumental values even when markets do not exist and when consumption and use are not involved. However, “altruistic man’s” genuine commitment to the well-being of others, particularly wildlife and future generations, challenges economic valuations at a fundamental level. In this case, self-interest and an indifference between states of the world are secondary and undefined respectively, since preferences are not based on tradeoffs between the welfare of others and self. The appropriateness of economic valuations rests solely with the empirical validity of the assumptions that give rise to economic man.
... might exist in one person. 39 37 Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (New York ...
11. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 20 > Issue: 3
Stan Godlovitch Things Change: So Whither Sustainability?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Two broad metaphysical perspectives deriving from Parmenides and Heraclitus have implications for our notion of sustainability. The Parmenidian defends a deepseated orderliness and permanence in things, while the Heraclitian finds only chance and change. Two further outlooks, the nomic (or the big-picture scientific) and the prudential, present differing accounts of our place in the world. While the nomic outlook accepts nothing privileged about the human perspective or even life itself, the prudential outlook is obviously welfare-centered. It is argued that nomic views, whether Parmenidian or Heraclitian, fail to provide any rationale for sustainability measures or concerns. The only such rationale comes from Parmenidian prudentialism, which, I argue, can operate only if it disowns at its peril the nomic point of view and couches sustainability entirely under the rubric of maximizing certain preferred opportunities drawn from collective self-love. But doing so merely evades rather than answers the tension imposed by the nomic Heraclitian for whom nothing lasts and nothing human counts specially in the measure. The liabilities of Parmenidian prudentialism are examined and found to be too great for any consistent notion of sustainability to bear.
...’s otherwise favorite rival, Richard Dawkins mused in like fashion that ...
12. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 2
John Nolt The Move from Is to Good in Environmental Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Moves from is to good—that is, principles that link fact to value—are fundamental to environmental ethics. The upshot is fourfold: (1) for nonanthropogenic goods, only those moves from is to good are defensible which conceive goodness as goodness for biotic entities; (2) goodness for nonsentient biotic entities is contribution to their autopoietic functioning; (3) biotic entities also function “exopoietically” to benefit related entities, and these exopoietic benefits are on average greater than their own goods; and (4) the most general is-to-good principles that are defensible (and hence the ones of greatest importance for environmental ethics) concern a realm of nonanthropogenic goodness that encompasses both living and nonliving nature.
13. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 18 > Issue: 4
J. Baird Callicott Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Recent deconstructive developments in ecology (doubts about the existence of unified communities and ecosystems, the diversity-stability hypothesis, and a natural homeostasis or “balance of nature”; and an emphasis on “chaos,” “perturbation,” and directionless change in living nature) and the advent of sociobiology (selfish genes) may seem to undermine the scientific foundations of environmental ethics, especially the Leopold land ethic. A reassessment of the Leopold land ethic in light of these developments (and vice versa) indicates that the land ethic is still a viable environmental ethic, if judiciously updated and revised.
...). Among reductive proponents Chandler cites Richard Dawkins, The ...
14. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 39 > Issue: 3
Oscar Horta Animal Suffering in Nature: The Case for Intervention
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Many people think we should refrain from intervening in nature as much as possible. One of the main reasons for thinking this way is that the existence of nature is a net positive. However, population dynamics teaches us that most sentient animals who come into existence in nature die shortly thereafter, mostly in painful ways (due to starvation, predation, and other reasons). Those who survive often suffer greatly due to natural causes. If sentient beings matter, this gives us reasons to intervene to prevent such harms. This counterintuitive conclusion can be opposed by arguing (1) that we should not care about nonhuman animals; (2) that other values, such as the existence of certain ecosystemic relations or of untouched wild areas, count for more than the interests of sentient beings; or (3) that intervention in nature cannot succeed. There are, however, strong reasons to reject these claims and to support significant intervention in nature for the sake of animals, despite our deep-rooted intuitions to the contrary.
...: Kessinger Publishing, 2004), p. 105, or Richard Dawkins, River Out of ...
15. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 10 > Issue: 1
Michael E. Zimmerman Quantum Theory, Intrinsic Value, and Panentheism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
J. Baird Callicott seeks to resolve the problem of the intrinsic value of nature by utilizing a nondualistic paradigm derived from quantum theory. His approach is twofold. According to his less radical approach, quantum theory shows that properties once considered to be “primary” and “objective” are in fact the products of interactions between observer and observed. Values are also the products of such interactions. According to his more radical approach, quantum theory’s doctrine of internal relations is the model for the idea that everything is intrinsically valuable because the “I” is intrinsically valuable and related to everything else. I argue that humanity’s treatment of nature will become respectful only as humanity’s awareness evolves toward nondualism, and that such nondualistic awareness will not be produced by changes in scientific theory alone. Nevertheless, as Callicott suggests, such changes may be harbingers of evolutionary trends in human awareness. I conclude with a sketch of how nondualism, especially in its panentheistic version, provides the basis for environmental ethics.
..., 1977) and The Whisperings Within (New York: Harper & Row, 1979); Richard Dawkins ...