Displaying: 1-20 of 3526 documents

0.376 sec

1. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 34 > Issue: 1/2
Anna Marmodoro Aristotle on Complex Perceptual Content. The Metaphysics of the Common Sense
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his theory of perception Aristotle is committed to the principle that there is a one-to-one correspondence between a sensible quality, the modification of a sense organ by that quality, and the content of the perceptual experience of it. But on the basis of this principle, simultaneous perceptions of different sensible qualities give rise only to distinct perceptual contents. This generates the problem of how we become aware of complex perceptual content, e.g. in discerning red from cold. This paper examines the alternative (although not equally explanatorily powerful) models that Aristotle offers in the De Anima and in his biological works to account for complex perceptual content.
...: The object of sight is the visible, and what is visible is (a) colour and (b ... is a one-to-one correspondence between a sensible quality, the modification of a ... modification of the appropriate special sense organ by the form.^ There is a one ...
2. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
J. Colin McQuillan A Merely Logical Distinction: Kant's Objection to Leibniz and Wolff
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Throughout his career, Immanuel Kant objects that Leibniz and Wolff make the distinction between sensible and intellectual cognition into a “merely logical” distinction. Although it is not clear that anyone in the Leibnizian-Wolffian tradition actually holds this view, Kant’s objection helps to define the “real” distinction between sensible and intellectual cognition that he defends in his inaugural dissertation in 1770. Kant raises the same objection against Leibniz and Wolff in the Critique of Pure Reason, but replaces the “real” distinction he defends in his inaugural dissertation with a new “transcendental” distinction between intuitions and concepts. This paper examines Kant’s objection to Leibniz and Wolff and the different alternatives he proposes, in order to highlight an important element in the development of his critical philosophy.
... and logic. 42 Because there is a science of the distinct cognition of the higher ... which belongs to the understanding as that of which there is a ... him to highlight the difference between the origin and content of sensible and ...
3. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 15 > Issue: 2
Jeffrey D. Gower The King of the Cosmos: Potentiality, Actuality, and the Logic of Sovereignty in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Λ
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper offers a deconstructive reading of the pure actuality of the un­moved mover of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Aristotle describes this first, unmoved principle of movement as a divine sovereign—the king of the cosmos—and maintains that the good governance of the cosmos depends on its unmitigated unity and pure actuality. It is striking, then, when Giorgio Agamben claims that Aristotle bequeathed the paradigm of sovereignty to Western philosophy not through his arguments for the pure actuality of the unmoved mover but rather through his description of the essence of potentiality. An interpretation of Aristotle’s account of potentiality in Metaphysics Theta therefore prepares the way for a deconstruction of the unity and pure actuality of the divine sovereign. I argue that the repetition of nous in Aristotle’s description of the divine thinking of thinking betrays traces of division and difference at the heart of divine sovereignty. If this is the case, then actuality and potentiality become indis­cernible at the level of the absolute and the sovereign corresponds to the bifurcated site of this indiscernibility.
...—covers over a difference between the activity of divine thinking and its ... Metaphysics Theta therefore prepares the way for a deconstruction of the unity and pure ... , “The rule of many is not good; let there be one ruler” (1076a4). 2 The quotation ...
4. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 2
Stéphanie Grégoire The Four Tools of Dialectic: Their Nature and their Use in Metaphysics ix
... difference between them is obvious at once, as in the case of ‘bright’ and ‘dark’: for a ... immature work. A comparison of passages of the Topics and Metaphysics should thus add ... translations, and would be inadequate in the context of the second tool, where it is a ...
5. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 1
J. Colin McQuillan The Remarriage of Reason and Experience in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article argues that Immanuel Kant recreates in his critical philosophy one of the most distinctive features of Christian Wolff’s rationalism—the marriage of reason and experience (connubium rationis et experientiae). The article begins with an overview of Wolff’s connubium and then surveys the reasons some of his contemporaries opposed the marriage of reason and experience, paying special attention to the distinctions between phenomena and noumena, sensible and intellectual cognition, and empirical and pure cognition that Kant employs in his inaugural dissertation On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World (1770). The final section of the article argues that, in the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), Kant rejects the anticonnubialist positions he defended in his inaugural dissertation and introduces a new account of the relation between reason and experience that recreates Wolff’s connubium within the context of his critical philosophy.
... the difference between a distinct concept and a confused one is ... introduces a new account of the relation between reason and experience that recreates ... , nor is there any experience, in which the a priori principles of our cognition are ...
6. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 22 > Issue: 1/2
Barbara V. Nunn Differences Between A- and B-Time
...-theories. The difference between A-time and B-time is not over different kinds of ... formulate the difference between \- and B-time is whether there are ... support for his assumption that the difference between A- and B-time is ...
7. Medieval Philosophy & Theology: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Alessandro D. Conti Analogy and Formal Distinction: On the Logical Basis of Wyclif s Metaphysics
... and works see A. B. Emden, A Biographical Register of the ... of transcendentals see A. B. Wolter, The Transcendentals and ... expression is a being, and whatever is the proper object of an act of signifying is ...
8. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 22 > Issue: 2
Mark Sentesy Are Potency and Actuality Compatible in Aristotle?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The belief that Aristotle opposes potency (dunamis) to actuality (energeia or entelecheia) has gone untested. This essay defines and distinguishes forms of the Opposition Hypothesis—the Actualization, Privation, and Modal—examining the texts and arguments adduced to support them. Using Aristotle’s own account of opposition, the texts appear instead to show that potency and actuality are compatible, while arguments for their opposition produce intractable problems. Notably, Aristotle’s refutation of the Megarian Identity Hypothesis applies with equal or greater force to the Opposition Hypothesis. For Aristotle, then, potency and actuality are compatible.
... [tēs diaphoras], and what is potential by the other. (Met. IX.6 1048a31–b6) 21 ... , then, there is first a typology of the Opposition Hypotheses ... ‘from’ and ‘to’ seem to indicate opposite ends of a continuum, the way hot is the ...
9. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 2
A.D. Carpenter Putting the Philebus’s Indispensable Method to Use
... one hand, and the limit’ (23c9-10). How much difference is there between looking ... Philebus 16a ff. Quite apart from the vexed issues of what the method is, and ... . Since there is a clear connection between the two, we may not need ...
10. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 22 > Issue: 2
Jussi Backman Being Itself and the Being of Beings: Reading Aristotle’s Critique of Parmenides (Physics 1.3) after Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The essay studies Aristotle’s critique of Parmenides (Physics 1.3) in the light of the Heideggerian account of Platonic-Aristotelian metaphysics as an approach to being (Sein) in terms of beings (das Seiende). Aristotle’s critique focuses on the presuppositions of the Parmenidean thesis of the unity of being. It is argued that a close study of the presuppositions of Aristotle’s own critique reveals an important difference between the Aristotelian metaphysical framework and the Parmenidean “protometaphysical” approach. The Parmenides fragments indicate being as such in the sense of the pure, undifferentiated “is there” (τὸ ἐόν)—as the intelligible accessibility of meaningful reality to thinking, prior to its articulation into determinate beings. For Aristotle, by contrast, “being itself” (αὐτὸ τὸ ὄν) has no other plausible meaning than “being-something-determinate as such” (τὸ ὅπερ ὄν τι), which itself remains equivocal. In this sense, Aristotle can indeed be said to conceive being in terms of beings, as the being-ness of determinate beings.
... present tense. There is no point in time at which being would be a thing of the ... subjectless and absolute sense ofthere is.” 26 Only a single account ... hand,” “is effectively (there)”) as a basic meaning of the Greek ...
11. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 11 > Issue: 2
Christopher P. Long Aristotle’s Phenomenology of Form: The Shape of Beings that Become
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Scholars often assume that Aristotle uses the terms morphē and eidos interchangeably. Translators of Aristotle's works rarely feel the need to carry the distinctionbetween these two Greek terms over into English. This article challenges the orthodox view that morphē and eidos are synonymous. Careful analysis of texts fromthe Categories, Physics, and Metaphysics in which these terms appear in close proximity reveals a fundamental tension of Aristotle's thinking concerning the being of natural beings. Morphē designates the form as inseparable from the matter in which it inheres, while eidos, because it is more easily separated from matter, is the vocabulary used to determine form as the ontological principle of the composite individual. The tension between morphē and eidos—between form as irreducibly immanent and yet somehow separate—is then shown to animate Aristotle's phenomenological approach to the being of natural beings. This approach is most clearly enacted in Aristotle's biology, a consideration of which concludes the essay.
... a tovde ti, and one principle is the lovgo~ of it, and also there is what is ... in the Categories there is a tendency to ascribe some degree of ... difference, then, between ei\do~ and morfhv in the Categories is that ei\do~, as that ...
12. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 32 > Issue: 2
Donald C. Lindenmuth Heidegger’s Platonism. By Mark A. Ralkowski
... live differently, to care for virtue and the health of their souls (Ap. 30a-b ... ’ (158). The difference is not just a difference of terminology. Plato rejected a ... irrational to feel great pain at the death of a loved one who is not ...
13. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 2
Lloyd P. Gerson The ‘Holy Solemnity’ of Forms and the Platonic Interpretation of Sophist
... difference between God and us is that (a) we are more than the activity of thinking ... undergoing g°nesiw, then the distinction between oÈs¤a and g°nesiw is no longer ... repudiation of the Friends’ doctrine. And if it is not a repudiation of their distinction ...
14. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1
David P. Hunt The ‘Problem of Fire’: Referring to Phenomena in Plato’s Timaeus
... the figures and asking what it is’ (50a6–b4). It is here, in cases of pure ... structure of our thought about the world’, and a ‘revisionary’ metaphysics, which ‘is ... traditional interpretation of 49b2–50a4 offered by Taylor and Cornford, while the B ...
15. Philosophical Inquiry: Volume > 28 > Issue: 3/4
Anton Friedrich Koch The Subjectivity Thesis and Its Corollaries
..., b, if and only //"every property of entity a is a property of ... to find the difference between times and locations in what exists at a ... be at one place at one time, there is an open question whether the location of ...
16. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
Terrence Thomson Kant’s Opus postumum and Schelling’s Naturphilosophie: The Very Idea
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper is about Kant’s late unfinished manuscript, Opus postumum (1796–1803) and some of the resonances it has with Schelling’s early Naturphiloso­phie (1797–1800). Most of the secondary literature on Opus postumum investigates its relation to the rest of Kant’s corpus, often framing the drafts as an attempt to fill a so-called “gap” in the Critical philosophy whilst ignoring the relationship it has to the wider landscape of late eighteenth century German philosophy. Whether Opus postumum may provide grounds for reviewing the relationship between Kant and Schelling’s Naturphilosophie, for example, is rarely discussed. Some scholars have remarked upon the striking parallels between Opus postumum and Naturphilosophie, but there has yet to appear a single monograph-length text on the relation. Whilst certainly “Schelling’s Post-Kantian confrontation with nature itself begins with the overthrow of the Copernican revolution” (Grant 2008, 6), what if Kant was himself overthrowing the Copernican revolution? In this paper, I will outline some of the points of contact to start from in support of posing this question.
... of Opus postumum, there is a deeper question that arises and forms the basis for ... print. The first time is in Kant’s own Metaphysics of Morals from ... be a step (passus) and not a leap (saltus). That is, the doctrine of ...
17. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Pascal Massie Saving Contingency: On Ockham’s Objection to Duns Scotus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
It is a common view that Ockham’s critique of Scotus’s position on the issue of contingency is “devastating,” for it seems obvious that a possibility that does notactualize is simply no possibility. This rejection however does not commit Ockham to necessitarism, for the consideration of the temporal discontinuity of volitions should suffice to save contingency. But does it? Is it the case that diachronic volitions (which Scotus also acknowledges) are sufficient?This essay argues that (1) the debate between Ockham and Scotus is not to be reduced to a logical disagreement (Scotus’s and Ockham’s modal logics are actually substantially similar) but is properly ontological inasmuch as it concerns the reduction and eventual identification of being with actuality and of actuality with reality in the sense of manifest; (2) the retrograding movement of truth from the present (Ockham’s 3rd suppositio) entails a temporal gap between present and future; and (3) Ockham’s solution depends on a conception of the will that cannot simply be identified with, and accounted for in terms of successive volitions.
... between present and future; and (3) Ockham’s solution depends on a conception of the ... that (1) the debate between Ockham and Scotus is not to be reduced to a logical ... nevertheless essentially twofold since it is at the same time a potency to be and not to be ...
18. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 42 > Issue: 1
Francesca Alesse The Predicative Role of ‘Being Good’ in Aristotle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The article proposes a renewed analysis of the texts in which Aristotle claims that the term ‘good’ is spoken of in many ways and more precisely in as many ways as there are categories. After a revision of the traditional interpretations, a new reading of the texts is advanced in the light of the theory of predication described in Top. 103 b20-38 and Metaph. 1017 a7-30. The conclusion is that in the Aristotelian passages on the multivocity of ‘good’, the word ‘good’ should not be meant as the predicate of categorially distinct realities, and therefore as a qualifying adjective, but itself as the subject of the question what is it? (τί ἐστι;) In this way, it is possible to advance the hypothesis that the homonymous notion of ‘good’ performs a predicative function, useful to the formulation of practical and prescriptive propositions.
...-34 and EE 1217b23-1218a1, should be the same as that of the subject of which it is ... described in Top. 103 b20-38 and Metaph. 1017 a7-30. The conclusion is that in the ... happiness and the highest good (is happiness the sum of different goods or a ...
19. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 1
Juan Manuel Garrido Jean-Luc Nancy’s Concept of Body
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article carries out a systematic exposition of the concept of the body in Jean-Luc Nancy, with all the risks of reduction that such an exposition entails. First it is necessary to return to Western philosophy’s founding text on living corporality, that is, Aristotle’s treatise on the soul. The oppositions that can be established between the Greek thinker’s psyche (soul) and Nancy’s dead Psyche are not so radical as may at first be thought: In both it is a question of thinking the soul as the difference, the retreat or departure in which the exposition of bodies consists. The article continues with an analysis of touch and the self and concludes with an elaboration of the idea of the body within the general program of the deconstruction of Christianity.
... and places itself out of itself. “With the soul, there is an effect of rupture, a ... thought: In both it is a question of thinking the soul as the difference, the ... exposition, and if the movement of such an exposition is always disruptive, a ...
20. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 17 > Issue: 2
David Bradshaw In What Sense Is the Prime Mover Eternal?
... experienced by the divine mind as a unity. But of course there is no difference between ... experience. A more ontological orientation is evident in the distinction between time and ... ’s view is available in De caelo i 9.279a15-22.Time is the number of motion, and ...