Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 81-100 of 3202 documents


articles

81. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Anna Gotlib, Orcid-ID Ruth Groenhout Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The COVID-19 pandemic and its conflict with science denialism raises the question of how philosophers teaching bioethics should respond to debates concerning truth, scientific evidence, and medical treatment raised by their students. We suggest that philosophical responses to the spread of serious disinformation in the health care context can be effectively explored in bioethics courses through discussions of informed consent, patient autonomy, the nature of scientific evidence, and moral responsibly for one’s views in ways that are especially important in the current pandemic era. Addressing these issues offers important epistemological grounding for students who will soon be making biomedical judgments and policies, as well as students who, like the rest of us, will be on the receiving end of those decisions. We argue that helping all of our students to understand the epistemological structures, and the moral consequences, of biomedicine and its detractors is a vital part of the professor’s responsibility.
82. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Robert Weston Siscoe, Orcid-ID Zachary Odermatt Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is no secret that we, as a society, struggle to have productive conversations about race and gender. Discussions about these issues are beset with obstacles, from the inherent power dynamics between conversation partners to the fear that participants feel about saying something harmful. One practice that can help address these difficulties is intergroup dialogue—sustained, small group discussions with participants from a variety of social identities. In this paper, we detail how we incorporated intergroup dialogue into a 120-student “Philosophy of Race, Class, and Gender” course, providing a blueprint for anyone who wants to help their students develop the ability to take part in fruitful conversations surrounding these challenging topics. We provide strategies for how to design intergroup dialogues to avoid many of the common pitfalls of such conversations, strategies that ultimately helped our students become more likely to initiate and participate in worthwhile discussions on race and gender. We expect our experiences to be especially helpful for instructors of large courses, where making time for small group dialogue is quite challenging, but many of the practices we used can also be adapted for smaller scale courses as well.

book reviews

83. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Russell W. Askren

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
84. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Vanessa Freerks

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
85. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Bertrand Guillaume

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
86. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
John Kinsey

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
87. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Barry Kleinberg

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
88. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Cecilea Mun

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
89. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Dale Murray

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
90. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Robert C. Robinson

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
91. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Theordore Stone Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
92. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Sandra Tomsons

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

93. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Galen Barry

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many students struggle to enter moral debates in a productive way because they automatically think of moral claims as ‘just opinions’ and not something one could productively argue about. Underlying this response are various versions of a muddled distinction between ‘facts’ and ‘opinions.’ This paper outlines a way to help students overcome their use of this distinction, thereby clearing an obstacle to true moral debate. It explains why the fact-opinion distinction should simply be scrapped, rather than merely sharpened. It then proposes a different distinction well suited to replace it. Finally, it outlines an activity which can be used to teach the new distinction, as well as a number of benefits to attempting the whole replacement process.
94. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
C. D. Brewer

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Here I describe a game that I use in my logic classes once we begin derivations. The game can help improve class dynamics, help struggling students recognizes they are not alone, open lines of communication between students, and help students of all levels prepare for exams. The game can provide struggling students with more practice with the fundamental rules of a logical system while also challenging students who excel at derivations. If students are struggling with particular rules or strategies in the system, the game can be tailored to address them. I explain how the game has evolved since I started using it, highlighting the pedagogical benefits of the changes I have made, and (in the appendix) I provide examples of the handouts I distribute and a “checklist” to use before, during, and after the game.
95. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Thomas Metcalf Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that colleges should include philosophy courses as general-education requirements. I begin by explaining the prima facie case against general-education requirements and the need for philosophers to defend their courses’ place in the general-education curriculum. Next, I present two arguments for philosophy as a general-education requirement. The first is the Argument from Content: that philosophy courses’ content tends to match the intended nature and purposes of general-education courses. The second is the Argument from Outcomes: that even if philosophy courses didn’t match the intended purposes of general-education courses, they would still be appropriate as general-education requirements, because there is empirical evidence that philosophy courses produce valuable skills and knowledge in students.
96. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jeff Mitchell

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The distinction between weak and strong forms of critical thinking is a hallmark of Richard Paul’s pedagogy. He maintains that good reasoning entails a personal commitment to fair-mindedness. In this brief essay, I argue that Paul’s conception of fair-mindedness conflates cognitive empathy with empathetic concern and altruism. One’s understanding another’s perspective by no means entails approving of it, and one may seek to better grasp this standpoint for purely selfish reasons. Depending upon the circumstances, the other could be one’s competitor, enemy, mark, or even intended victim. This implies that while we may wish that the world were otherwise, even very bad people can be highly effective critical thinkers.
97. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jake Wright

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that campus closures and shifts to online instruction in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic created an obligation to offer courses asynchronously. This is because some students could not have reasonably foreseen circumstances making continued synchronous participation impossible. Offering synchronous participation options to students who could continue to participate thusly would have been unfair to students who could not participate synchronously. I also discuss why ex post facto consideration of this decision is warranted, noting that similar actions may be necessary in the future and that other tough pedagogical cases share important similarities with this case.

book reviews

98. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Patrick D. Anderson

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
99. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Errol Ball Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
100. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Teresa Baron

view |  rights & permissions | cited by