Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 41-51 of 51 documents


articles

41. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Gary Mar

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Anselm claimed that his Proslogion was a “single argument” sufficient to prove “that God truly exists,” that God is “the supreme good requiring nothing else,” as well as to prove “whatever we believe regarding the divine Being.” In this paper we show how Anselm’s argument in the Proslogion and in his Reply to Gaunilo can be reconstructed as a single argument. A logically elegant result is that the various stages of Anselm’s argument are validated by standard axioms from contemporary modal logic.
42. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Richard Swinburne Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I have argued in many places that a carefully articulated version of Descartes’ argument to show that he is essentially an immaterial soul is sound. It is conceivable that I who am currently conscious continue to exist without my body, and that can only be if there is currently a non-bodily part of me which alone is essential for me. Recent counter-arguments of Alston and Smythe, Moser and van der Nat, Zimmerman, and Shoemaker are rejected.
43. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Phillip Cary

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Our concept of knowing of other persons ought to include respect for them. Since respect implies considering whether what they say is true, I propose that believing others’ words is a necessary condition of knowing them. I explore the contribution such belief makes to knowledge of other persons, as well as some surprising but welcome implications, including theological consequences.
44. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Andrew V. Jeffrey

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Richard Gale, in On the Nature and Existence of God, offers several reasons why an “historical-cum-indexical” theory of reference cannot be appropriate in explaining how people refer to God. The present paper identifies five distinct lines of argument in Gale, attempts to clarify several important desiderata for a successful theory of reference, and argues that Gale fails to discharge the burden of proof he has assumed, leaving the most important features of Alston’s “direct reference” theory untouched. Nevertheless, it is conceded that some consequences of Alston’s theory are quite counter-intuitive. The paper therefore concludes with a consideration of two alternatives: either taking a hard, Alstonian line in conflict with people’s linguistic intuitions, or striking a compromise with descriptivism along lines similar to those found in Gareth Evans’s paper, “The Causal Theory of Names.”
45. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Andrew P. Porter

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Ian Barbour sees four ways to relate science and religion: (1) conflict, (2) disjunction or independence, (3) dialogue, and (4) synthesis or integration. David Burrell posits three ways to construe religious language, as (a) univocal, (b) equivocal, or (c) analogous. The paper contends that Barbour’s (1) and (4) presuppose Burrell’s (a), Barbour's (2) presupposes Burrell’s (b), and Barbour’s (3) presupposes Burrell’s (c), and it explores some of the implications for each alternative.
46. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
John Lamont

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The paper considers Renee Descartes’ assertion that believing that God exists because the Bible says so, and believing that what the Bible says is true because God says it, involves circular reasoning. It argues that there is no circularity involved in holding these beliefs, and maintains that the appearance of circularity results from an equivocation. It considers a line of argument that would defend the rationality of holding these beliefs, but does not try to prove its soundness.

book reviews

47. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Graham Oppy

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
48. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Stephen N. Dunning

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
49. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Paul J. Weithman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
50. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1
Ronald E. Hustwit

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

notes and news

51. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 13 > Issue: 1

view |  rights & permissions | cited by