Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 97 documents


articles

21. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Steven L. Reynolds

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A traditional diagnosis of the error in the Cartesian skeptical arguments holds that they exploit our tendencies to take a representationalist view of perception. Thinking (perhaps not too clearly) that we perceive only our own sensory states, it seems to us that our perceptual beliefs about physical objects must be justified qua explanations of those sensory states. Such justification requires us to have reasons to reject rival explanations, such as the skeptical hypotheses, which we lack. However, those who adopt the direct realist view of perception still find these arguments plausible, although, according to this diagnosis, they shouldn’t. To avoid this objection, I argue that the Cartesian skeptical arguments exploit, not our representationalist tendencies, but our habits for evaluating causal explanatory justifications.
22. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
David Hunter

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A natural view is that linguistic understanding is a source of justification or evidence: that beliefs about the meaning of a text or speech act are prima facie justified when based on states of understanding. Neglect of this view is largely due to the widely held assumption that understanding a text or speech act consists in knowledge or belief. It is argued that this assumption rests, in part, on confusing occurrent states of understanding and dispositions to understand. It is then argued that occurrent states of understanding are not states of belief of knowledge since a subject may fail to believe that a text or speech act means what she understands it to mean if she doubts the reliability or truthfulness of that understanding. States of understanding, it is maintained, belong in the same epistemic category as states of perception and memory.
23. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Steven Rieber

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Theories of personal identity try to explain what the identity of a person necessarily consists in, but frequently leave open what kind of necessity is at issue. This paper is concerned with conceptual necessity. It proposes an analysis of the concept of personal identity in terms of a definite description. The analysis coheres with out judgments about clear cases and explains why cases of division seem indeterminate. The apparent indeterminacy results from attempting to apply a definite description to a situation in which more than one object would satisfy the description. The definite description analysis also explains the strengths of the influential no-branching theory. while avoiding the problems with that view. The no-branching theory is in effect a second-order analysis, i.e., a combination of the definite description analysis of personal identity plus a Russellian analysis of the definite description.

book symposium:

24. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Akeel Bilgrami

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Michael Williams

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Gary Ebbs

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
27. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Derk Pereboom

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
28. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Jeff Malpas

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Akeel Bilgrami

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Michael Tye

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Frank Jackson

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Ned Block

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
33. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Sydney Shoemaker

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
34. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Michael Tye

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

review essays

35. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Bernard Berofsky

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
36. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Michael E. Bratman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

critical notices

37. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Frederick Stoutland

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Richard M. Gale

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Patrick Grim

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 3
Keith Butler

view |  rights & permissions | cited by