Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 112 documents


essay review

21. Arendt Studies: Volume > 6
Eric Ghosh

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews

22. Arendt Studies: Volume > 6
Fanny Söderbäck

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. Arendt Studies: Volume > 6
Jeanette Joy Harris

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

24. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
James Barry

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book panel exile, statelessness, and migration: playing chess with history from hannah arendt to isaiah berlin by seyla benhabib

25. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Lyndsey Stonebridge

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The failure of post-war institutions to fully grasp the depth and permanence of the placeless condition in the twentieth-century is at least in part responsible for the re-emergence of camps, barbed wire, sunken boats, and separated children in our own. As Seyla Benhabib demonstrates brilliantly, none of key intellectual exiles at the center of her book believed that political thought could simply accommodate the age of the refugee: the terms under which it operated had to shift with the moving world. I argue that there is an important kind of border poetics at work in these accounts of exile, migration and statelessness and within Benhabib’s analysis of the challenges that the placeless condition presents to the institutions of law and democracy today. This is no-coincidence. The modern history of placelessness required—and requires—a political imagination, and a language, that we are yet to fully appreciate or articulate. The wager of Benhabib’s book is how we might cultivate a poetics of exile which relinquishes claims to sweeping universalism whilst imagining the new forms we so urgently need to keep political life open to the differences and otherness that is its lifeblood.
27. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Martin Shuster

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This is a response to Seyla Benhabib’s Exile, Stateless, and Migration. I focus on Benhabib’s engagement with Arendt and her assessment of stateless persons in addition to what such a discussion suggests for the scope of our historical inquiry.
28. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
David Ingram

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article examines the theoretical pathways connecting Benhabib’s thoughts on ethical normativity, human rights, legality, democracy, liberalism, pluralism, and the tragedy of the political. It endorses Benhabib’s dialectical treatment of these paradoxical political tropes but notes a possible unresolved tension in her discussion of the ambiguous moral and legal nature of human rights. I propose a pluralist approach to the moral grounding of legal human rights that might be at odds with Benhabib’s approach.
29. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Claire Elise Katz

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In her chapter on Judith Butler’s Parting Ways, Seyla Benhabib revisits not only Levinas’s statements on Israel but also Butler’s response to them. Several of Levinas’s statements on the State of Israel were made either before the state came into existence or just as it was forming. And several of Levinas’s statements about the hostility that Israel faces were made not about the Palestinian but about the threats to Israel from its neighboring Arab states. In this essay, I revisit those statements and Butler’s response, in order to place them in their proper context. My aim is to ask what we can learn by revisiting these comments when placed in their original context as opposed to thinking of them as comments about Israel in its more contemporary struggles.
30. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Arie M. Dubnov Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Reflections on Seyla Benhabib’s a. Exile, Statelessness, and Migration: Playing Chess with History from Hannah Arendt to Isaiah Berlin. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2018.
31. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Seyla Benhabib

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

32. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Hannes Bajohr Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Judith Shklar wrote about Hannah Arendt throughout her career. However, her nuanced readings are often ignored by scholars who prefer to depict both philosophers as stark counter-images. In this paper, I offer a more complex comparison on the basis of all of Shklar’s writings about Arendt. Shklar’s critique is grounded in what she sees as the Romantic strand in Arendt’s thought, which she identifies with a metaphysical, elitist, and aestheticizing stance towards politics, a distaste for modernity, and a nostalgia for Greek antiquity. For Shklar, this position comes to the fore both in what she believes to be Arendt’s purely therapeutic notion of revolution as well as the rejection of her own Jewish identity. Nevertheless, Shklar also admired Arendt’s insights about exile and her appreciation of Kant. Through her sustained critique of Arendt, Shklar developed her own conception of a realist, rights-affirming, and anti-metaphysical liberalism.
33. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Bridget Allan

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this article, I bring together Hannah Arendt’s and Simone de Beauvoir’s respective theories of political judgment to evaluate the problems that arise from their accounts of judgment in praxis. To do so, I compare Arendt’s Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil on Adolf Eichmann’s trial in Israel and Beauvoir’s “An Eye for an Eye” on Robert Brasillach’s trial in France. In approaching the dilemmas of judgment in theory, both share a commitment to preserving freedom by virtue of our human plurality. In practice, however, both respectively demand the death penalty for Eichmann and Brasillach. I identify three distinct failures of political judgment in praxis: from the accused, the courts, and Arendt and Beauvoir, respectively. I contend that Arendt and Beauvoir fail to appropriately judge Eichmann and Brasillach by arguing for their execution, because it constitutes a form of political violence that undermines their theoretical accounts of judgment.
34. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
James Risser

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
35. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Kyu-hyun Jo

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Hannah Arendt’s conception of violence in On Violence ignores cases in which violence becomes an expression of power. Through my discussion of a government’s use of violence to control criminal violence and the Algerian Revolution, I argue that an Arendtian communicative relationship between power and violence is unrealistic; a decision to use violence can arise within a government bureaucracy or between an anti-colonial group and their supporters, but not between a colonial oppressor and the oppressed. The decision to use violence is a product of power and cannot actually expect a literal public support. Since the decision arises from the power an entity has over others and the need to maintain power, it is unrealistic for power to rule absolutely or for violence to disappear because there is absolute power. Arendt’s central claim is insufficient because it does not consider how using violence is a decision arising from power.

review essays

36. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
John Douglas Macready

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
37. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Manjeet Ramgotra

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book review

38. Arendt Studies: Volume > 5
Christopher Peys

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

39. Arendt Studies: Volume > 4
James Barry

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

margaret canovan: commemoration

40. Arendt Studies: Volume > 4
James Barry

view |  rights & permissions | cited by