Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 181-200 of 1823 documents


book reviews

181. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 4
Bryan Cross

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
182. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 4
Kevin Vallier

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
183. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 4
Alicia Finch

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
184. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 4
Stewart Goetz

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
185. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 4
Eleanor Helms

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

186. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Kyla Ebels-Duggan

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In the Groundwork Kant asserts that the fundamental moral principle must be a principle of autonomy. He dismisses theistic principles, along with all other competitors to his Categorical Imperative, claiming that they are heteronomous. I argue that the best case for this Kantian conclusion conflates our access to the reasons for our commitments with an ability to state these reasons such that they could figure in an argument. This conflation, in turn, results from a certain Kantian conception of inclination, and its role in our moral psychology. These are views that we ought to reject. Having done so, we will see that a theistic ethics based on desire or love for God need not face a distinctive problem of heteronomy.
187. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Joshua Cockayne, David Efird

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
People of faith, particularly in the Judeo-Christian tradition, worship corporately at least as often, if not more so, than they do individually. Why do they do this? There are, of course, many reasons, some having to do with personal preference and others having to do with the theology of worship. But, in this paper, we explore one reason, a philosophical reason, which, despite recent work on the philosophy of liturgy, has gone underappreciated. In particular, we argue that corporate worship enables a person to come to know God better than they would otherwise know him in individual worship.
188. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Anthony Bolos

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I challenge the assumption that human uniqueness of the sort motivated by the doctrine of the imago Dei is incompatible with contemporary views in evolutionary biology. I first develop a functionalist account of the image of God and then argue that image bearing is a contingently imposed function. Humans, chosen by God to bear his image, are unique in that they alone possess an ideal range of image bearing capacities. This ideal range makes humans well-suited for the role of image bearing.
189. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Perry Hendricks

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Trent Dougherty has argued that commonsense epistemology and skeptical theism are incompatible. In this paper, I explicate Dougherty’s argument, and show that (at least) one popular form of skeptical theism is compatible with commonsense epistemology.
190. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
William Hasker Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Scott Williams’s Latin Social model of the Trinity holds that the trinitarian persons have between them a single set of divine mental powers and a single set of divine mental acts. He claims, nevertheless, that on his view the persons are able to use indexical pronouns such as “I.” This claim is examined and is found to be mistaken.
191. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Merold Westphal

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Two reasons are given for speaking of “reason” even where Kierkegaard’s pseudonym, Climacus, speaks of “understanding.” First, we are dealing with a significant contribution to a centuries-old discussion of an issue that goes by the name of “faith and reason.” Second, whereas Kant and Hegel sharply distinguish mere understanding from reason, no such distinction is at work in Kierkegaard’s text. At issue is the quite different distinction of unaided human reason and divine revelation. It is not just any notion of reason that is the target of Kierkegaard’s critique, but an autonomous reason, independent of revelation, that claims hegemony over biblical faith in both its popular and academic forms. This hegemony expresses itself in both outright rejection of and radical reinterpretation of elements of biblical faith.

book reviews

192. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Kevin Timpe

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
193. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Dolores G. Morris

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

194. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
David Vander Laan

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In much of Christian thought humans are taken to have an ultimate end, understood as the highest attainable good. Christians also anticipate “the life everlasting.” Together these ideas generate a paradox. If the end can be reached in a finite amount of time, some longer-lasting state will be better still, so the purported end is not the highest good after all. But if the end is to possess some good forever, then it will never be reached. So it seems an everlasting being cannot have an ultimate end—a conclusion that apparently makes human life pointless. How can the paradox be solved?
195. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Brian Leftow

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
After defining presentism, I consider four arguments that presentism and divine atemporality are incompatible. I identify an assumption common to the four, ask what reason there is to consider it true, and argue against it.
196. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Daniel J. McKaughan

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Faith plays a valuable role in sustaining relationships through various kinds of challenges, including through evidentially unfavorable circumstances and periods of significant doubt. But if, as is widely assumed, both faith in God and faith that God exists require belief that God exists, and if one’s beliefs are properly responsive to one’s evidence, the capacity for faith to persevere amidst significant and well-grounded doubt will be fairly limited. Taking Mother Teresa as an exemplar of Christian faith and exploring the close connection between faith and faithfulness in the context of committed covenantal relationships, I set out a view of Relational Faith that does not assume that faith requires belief and allows wide room for honestly wrestling with doubt from within the Judeo-Christian tradition.
197. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Hamid Vahid

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Philosophical responses to religious diversity range from outright rejection of divine reality to claims of religious pluralism. In this paper, I challenge those responses that take the problem of religious diversity to be merely an instance of the general problem of disagreement. To do so, I will take, as my starting point, William Alston’s treatment of the problems that religious diversity seems to pose for the rationality of theistic beliefs. My main aim is to highlight the cognitive penetrability of religious experience as a major source of such problems. I conclude by examining the consequences of cognitive penetration for the reliability of the monotheistic doxastic practice.
198. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Nikolaus Breiner

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to Eleonore Stump, Thomas Aquinas rejects a “popular” (roughly, penal substitutionary) account of the atonement. For Stump’s Aquinas, God does not require satisfaction or punishment for human sin, and the function of satisfaction is remedial, not juridical or penal. Naturally, then, Aquinas does not, on this reading, see Christ’s passion as having saving effect in virtue of Christ substitutionally bearing the punishment for human sin that divine justice requires. I argue that Stump is incorrect. For Aquinas, divine justice does require satisfaction; satisfaction involves punishment ( poena) and has a penal function; and one way Christ’s death has saving effect is in virtue of his satisfying that requirement on people’s behalf. Christ saves by “paying our debt,” bearing in the place of humans the penalty or punishment required by divine justice. My argument implies that Aquinas’s account of satisfaction in the atonement significantly resembles key aspects of Stump’s “popular account”—and of the Penal Substitution Theory it represents.

book reviews

199. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
James G. Hanink

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
200. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Anna Marmodoro

view |  rights & permissions | cited by