Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 47 documents


articles

1. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Travis Dumsday

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
J. L. Schellenberg’s “problem of divine hiddenness” has generated much discussion. Swinburne has replied with his “responsibility argument,” according to which God allows some nonresistant nonbelief in order to foster the good of human responsibility, with some people tasked with leading others to belief in God. Schellenberg has supplied detailed replies to Swinburne. My goal is to provide a new formulation of the responsibility argument that defuses Schellenberg’s objections.
2. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Gregory L. Bock

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The proper interpretation of Hume’s argument against miracles in Section 10 of An Inquiry concerning Human Understanding has been heavily debated. In this paper, I argue that Hume’s main argument has the intended conclusion that there can never be a sufficient justification for believing that a miracle has occurred on the basis of testimony sufficient to make it a basis for a religion. I also consider and argue against other common readings.
3. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Bruce Reichenbach

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Interreligious dialogue presupposes that discourse functions the same for both parties. I argue that what makes Christian-Buddhist dialogue so difficult is that whereas Christians have a realist view of theoretical concepts, Buddhists generally do not. The evidence for this is varied, including the Buddha’s own refusal to respond to metaphysical questions and the Buddhist constructionist view of reality. I reply to two objections, that Buddhists do conduct metaphysical debate, and that the Buddha adopted a correspondence rather than a pragmatic theory of truth. In the end I develop the implications of this realist/nonrealist dichotomy for commencing and conducting interreligious dialogue.

philosophical notes

4. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
William Lane Craig

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
While declaring philosophy to be dead, Hawking and Mlodinow are deeply engaged in philosophical speculation. Their treatment of the origin and fine-tuning of the universe, though unsympathetic to theism, turns out upon examination to be quite supportive of natural theology.
5. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Patrick T. Smith

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
J. L. Schellenberg has provided a rigorous and robust philosophical defense of religious skepticism through various modes of reasoning and employs an epistemic defeat strategy that appeals to unrecognized evidence. He contends on this framework that reason requires religious skepticism. This essay focuses on Schellenberg’s basic epistemic defeat strategy. I argue that his methodology is problematic because his key skeptical argument rests on an equivocation on the notion of total evidence, which makes it difficult to implement his epistemic defeat strategy in favor of his claim that reason requires us to be religious skeptics.
6. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Francis J. Beckwith

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay is a review of Edward Feser’s Aquinas: A Beginner’s Guide. In the first part, the author summarizes the book’s five chapters, drawing attention to Feser’s application of Aquinas’s thought to contemporary philosophical problems. Part 2 is dedicated to Feser’s Thomistic analysis of Intelligent Design (ID). The author explains Feser’s case and why Aquinas’s “Fifth Way,” which is often labeled a “design argument,” depends on a philosophy of nature that ID’s methods implicitly reject.
7. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Marie George

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that Edward Feser misconstrues the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition on issues relevant to the arguments for God’s existence that proceed from finality in nature because he misapplies the A-T view that ordering to an end is inherent in natural things: (1) Feser speaks as if human action in no way serves as a model for understanding action for an end in nature; (2) he misreads, and ultimately undermines, the Fifth Way, by substituting intrinsic end-directedness in place of end-directedness; (3) he overlooks striking similarities between Paley’s argument from design and the Fifth Way. He also fails to consider the role of the good in the Fifth Way.
8. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Kevin Corcoran

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In his book Defending Life, Francis Beckwith claims that the question of personhood and human nature is the central question in the abortion debate. He further asserts that the unborn entity, from the moment of conception, is a full-fledged member of the human community. In this paper I try to show that the argument Beckwith offers for the moral wrongness of abortion in Defending Life is unpersuasive, his elucidation of key terms question-begging, and his claims concerning embryology and zygotic (and postzygotic) development highly controversial.
9. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Gary Hartenburg

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In When Athens Met Jerusalem, John Mark Reynolds makes (1) a claim about Plato’s account of the relation between myth and argument, (2) a claim about Plato’s account of knowledge and science, and (3) a claim about the relation between faith and reason. I criticize each of these claims. Regarding the first claim, I show that Reynolds’s explanation of the role of a person’s experience of Platonic forms is unclear. Regarding the second, I indicate some tensions between the antirealist character of Platonic philosophy of science and Reynolds’s insistence that some claims about the empirical world are true. Lastly, I attempt to clarify Reynolds’s explanation of the relation between faith and reason by thinking of them as two parts of a single whole whose goal is to comprehend truths about God.

book reviews

10. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
J. B. Stump

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Patrick Arnold

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
W. David Beck

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Michael McFall

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2
Tawa J. Anderson

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

15. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 2

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

16. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 1
Craig J. Hazen

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

17. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 1
R. J. Snell

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this essay I argue that Thomas Aquinas is not as naively optimistic about the noetic effects of sin as is often portrayed by standard neo-Calvinist objections. Still, his metaphysics of the human person requires some development to better explain the mind’s impairment by sin, a development made possible by the work of Bernard Lonergan and the resulting Lonergan/Aquinas (L/A) model of the noetic effects of sin.
18. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 1
John B. Howell III

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this essay I examine the notion of forgiveness as found in Søren Kierkegaard’s Works of Love. After detailing the work of forgiveness in hiding the multitude of sins, I examine forgiveness as an example of Kierkegaard’s concept of redoubling. Then I relate Kierkegaard’s concept of forgiveness to his concept of hope. Throughout I emphasize the relation between forgiveness and neighbor love, which Kierkegaard views as an essential component of forgiveness. This emphasis counters the prevailing notion in the literature on forgiveness, which views forgiveness as solely concerned with the relinquishing of negative emotions. For Kierkegaard, while this relinquishing is no doubt part of forgiveness, true forgiveness must include love for one’s neighbor.
19. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 1
Aaron Bunch

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that Kant’s own views—his commitment to happiness as part of a transcendent highest good, his view of the afterlife as a place of moral striving, and his conception of the “absolute unity” of rational and animal natures in a human person—commit him to belief in an embodied afterlife. This belief is just as necessary for conceiving the possibility of the highest good as the beliefs in personal immortality, freedom, and God’s existence, and thus it too is a “practical postulate” in Kant’s sense.
20. Philosophia Christi: Volume > 12 > Issue: 1
Shawn Bawulski

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Logically consistent responses to the problem of hell are readily available. The Christian theologian should seek to go beyond these minimal criteria, providing a response that is also plausible and is harmonious with both Scripture and the tradition. In this paper I will examine annihilationism and two forms of traditionalism, assessing each view’s success not only in defending against the logical problem of hell, but also success with these additional criteria. I will suggest that a refined version of the traditional view best succeeds.