Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 485 documents


book reviews

1. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 2
Forrest Clingerman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

2. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Jayson Jimenez Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay reflects on my academic work and personal experience as a bonsai enthusiast. Specifically, I plan to point out how Deleuzian theory informs my bonsai practice. First, I situate bonsai gardening as an encounter with the vegetal world. Then I consider this encounter as a form of Deleuzian becoming. Becoming reifies a transformation of the two species to become another version of itself—one that occurs between a bonsai and its carer. As a bonsai carer myself, I find becoming as a precise illustration of my relationship with bonsais; hence, a vegetal encounter in the making.
3. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Monika Kaup

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Davi Kopenawa and Bruce Albert’s 2010 collaborative work, The Falling Sky: Words of a Yanomami Shaman, centers on a prophetic warning of impending apocalyptic collapse due to anthropogenic environmental destruction. An indigenous contribution to the contemporary burst of eco-apocalyptic writing and the search for a new ecological social order, The Falling Sky challenges the temporal vector of Euroamerican eco-apocalypticism. Instead of the teleological axis of anthropocentric temporality (the emergence of homo sapiens as the pinnacle of evolution), it refers us to a temporality of terrestrial life, where homo sapiens is just one more living species in the web of life.
4. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Michael J. Reno

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I present an interpretation of Adorno’s concept of nature that prompts a confrontation with both the domination of nature and the romanticization of nature. This interpretation would situate a normative stance toward human engagement with nature not in the idealization of a pre-social or pre-human nature, but in the (missed) possibilities of past human engagements with non-human nature. Experience of art, such as Edward Burtynsky’s photography, can push us toward such a stance. This stance forces a reconsideration of the dominant form of self-preservation in most contemporary societies; nature cannot be realized until our species understands itself as a species.
5. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Olli Pitkänen

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Sean McGrath has produced an interesting interpretation of Renaissance Hermeticism in the context of environmental philosophy. By recovering this esoteric current he combines deep ecological criticism of anthropocentrism with humanistic critique of one-sidedly ecocentric views. After summarizing McGrath’s position and arguing for its profound potential, I will point out a problem in McGrath’s use of one of his key conceptions: disenchantment. Countering McGrath, I argue that the conception of disenchantment is not suitable for distinguishing overly ideological or superficial forms of esotericism from those with actual philosophical and political potential.
6. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Simon Nørgaard Iversen Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Recent posthuman theories of nature recognition seek to move beyond Hegel’s anthropological starting point. This article serves as a critical rejoinder to such posthuman attempts by taking aim at posthumanism’s flat ontology and concept of agency. Instead, it is suggested that a genuine Hegelian starting point is better suited to discern the complex interrelationship between the human and nonhuman. It is argued that a Hegelian theory of recognition that takes Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature and Philosophy of Mind into consideration can give nature its due while simultaneously preserving humans as the primary locus of agency in answering current environmental problems.
7. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Ana Vieyra

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I suggest an alternative reading of the value of Hegel’s systematic approach to nature from the perspective of environmental philosophy. Taking the paradigmatic example of the “new materialist” ontologies, I present the problems with an inflationary justification for the argument for the need of a shift in the “scientific” representation of nature. On the basis of these problems, I suggest that Hegel’s view of nature as axiologically impotent sheds light into why emancipatory environmental theory needs not hinge on a determinate understanding of nature. In my reading, this rejection can be harmonized with the asymmetric nature of our responsibility towards non-human nature.

book reviews

8. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Sara Louise Tonge

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Anna Myers

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Chandler D. Rogers

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Lanbin Feng

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Shoshana McIntosh Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Lewis Rosenberg

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Ben Larsen

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Isabelle Bishop

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

16. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Jeremy Bendik-Keymer Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Julia D. Gibson Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Building off Manulani Aluli-Meyer’s theory of holographic epistemology, this article explores how our understanding of intergenerational justice shifts when informed by relational interspecies ethics and nonlinear temporalities. Both intergenerational and interspecies ethics are greatly enriched if the dead, the living, and those yet-to-be are not (only) distinct generations of beings along a linear sequence but coexistent facets of every being. The second focal point of this article concerns what holographic epistemology reveals about Dipesh Chakrabarty’s notion of the planetary. Ultimately, the article argues that holographic intergenerational ethics highlight the need for a third earthly domain beyond the planet and the globe.
18. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Danielle Celermajer, Orcid-ID Christine J. Winter Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In A Climate of History Dipesh Chakrabarty locates Kant’s speculative reading of Genesis as “the Enduring Fable” furnishing the background for human domination and earthly destruction. Writing from the fable’s “ruins,” Chakrabarty urges the elaboration of new fables that provide the background ethics and meanings required to recast relations between humans and the natural world. Responding to Chakrabarty’s challenge, we outline two “fables” based first in the oft ignored Genesis 2, and second, in Matauranga Māori. Although marginalised, these extant fables provide the imaginary for radically other ways of being human in a more-than-human world in turmoil.
19. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Thomas Nail

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay shows how a new materialist theory of the Earth side-steps the distinction between the global and the planetary that structures Chakrabarty’s historiography. It advocates for a non-binary-generating approach to our planetary situation grounded in the philosophy of motion.
20. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Neil Brenner, Orcid-ID Elizabeth Chatterjee, Orcid-ID Jeremy Bendik-Keymer Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by