Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


articles

1. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
2. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
David S. Oderberg

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Central to recent debate over the Kalam Cosmological Argument, and over the origin of the universe in general, has been the issue of whether the universe began to exist and, if so, how this is to be understood. Adolf Grünbaum has used two cosmological models as a basis for arguing that the universe did not begin to exist according to either of them. Concentrating in this paper on the second (“open interval”) model, I argue that he is wrong on both counts. I give metaphysical considerations for rejecting Grünbaum’s interpretationof the second model and offer a definition of the beginning of existence of an object that improves on prior formulations and that is adequate to show how the universe can indeed be seen to have begun to exist. I conclude with a more general metaphysical discussion of the beginning of the universe and of the Kalam Cosmological Argument.
3. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Michael Tkacz

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Contemporary biologists generally agree with E. O. Wilson’s claim that “reduction is the traditional instrument of scientific analysis.” This is certainly true of Michael Ruse, who has attempted to provide a Darwinian account of human scientific knowledge in terms of epigenetic rules. Such an account depends on the characterization of natural objects as the chance concatenations of material elements, making natural form an effect rather than a cause of the object. This characterization, however, can be shown to be false in that it is self-refuting in its exclusion of formal cause. The retorsive argument for formal cause dialectically shows that any attempt to explain a natural object depends on the identification of form as the cause of the intelligibility of the object. It follows that Darwinian explanations of the products of human culture, such as science, cannot consistently treat form as an effect rather than a cause.
4. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Montague Brown

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper focuses on Aquinas’s doctrine of individuation as it applies to human beings. There are three main sections. In the first, the general lines of Aquinas’s doctrine of individuation are presented in the context of discussing an article by Joseph Owens and some other recent work on individuation. I argue for form as the primary principle of individuation and specify the uniqueness of human individuality by reference to the degrees of perfection among things. The second section focuses on three ways in which a meditation on our form—the rational soul—is fruitful for understanding what makes us individuals. Here I consider, in turn, the three distinctive activities of human reason—theoretical, moral, and aesthetic. Each activity is presented as it relates to three levels of perfection in the human being. In the third section, I bring up three pertinent objections to my thesis and suggest answers to them.
5. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Frederick E. Crowe

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As soon as we attend to the subject, either by asking questions or by making statements about it, we ipso facto make the subject the object of our attention. The question then is whether we can get behind the subject as object and attain the subject as subject. Is the project not self-refuting? For an answer I invoke the parallel case of insight into insight. We cannot imagine the act of insight and so cannot understand it directly, but we can construct symbols of insight, understand them, and thus indirectly achieve some understanding of it. Lonergan made five attempts to achieve insight into insight; the article examines them one by one and applies them to our parallel case in order to conclude that there is a meaningful sense in which we may attain and speak of the subject as subject.
6. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Sarah E. Glenn

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Richard Rorty places William James in the same category of thinkers as Hegel. These thinkers, he claims, do not believe that philosophical discussion involves any reference to a reality external to their dialogue. Rorty’s claim initially seems justified, for Jamesdoes after all speak of the malleability of reality and insists that reality is part of experience. However, the fact that reality is part of experience does not necessarily mean that it is created by experience. Indeed, James insists that the reality that limits truth is “found, not manufactured,” and the flexibility of truth cannot be attributed to the lack of an external reality but rather results from the interplay of thought and reality in determining truth.
7. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
J. P. Moreland

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The literature on the Knowledge Argument exhibits considerable confusion about the precise nature of the argument. I contend that a clarification of the essence of self-presenting properties provides an explanation of this confusion such that the confusion itself is evidence for dualism. I also claim that Mary gains six different sorts of knowledge after gaining sight, and I show how this claim provides a response to a physicalist undercutting defeater for the Knowledge Argument. I try to show that this defeater is inadequate due to its failure to capture the epistemic richness of what happens to Mary. Finally, I indicate how my enriched version of the Knowledge Argument provides grounds for rejecting those varieties of physicalism that eschew a depiction of phenomenal propertiesas intrinsic attributes a subject exemplifies in favor of a view that treats them as functional roles a subject realizes.

feature review article

8. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
John J. Davenport

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews and notices

9. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
John J. Drummond

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Raymond Dennehy

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Antony Flew

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
W. Norris Clarke

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Fergus Kerr

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
C. C. W. Taylor

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Brendan Sweetman

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Margaret Urban Walker

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Michael Kelly

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2

view |  rights & permissions | cited by