Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 46 documents


editor’s introduction

1. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
James E. Roper

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

essays

2. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Susan Anderson

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I argue that several features of Big Business in the United States, and its influence on our society, have caused far too many Americans to stop thinking about what is morally right as they choose their actions. An ethical vacuum has been created that Big Business has been only too glad to fill with questionable values that Americans have absorbed without consciously embracing. The time is right, and the stakes have never been higher, for us to reflect on our values and change our thinking and behavior. Big Business and Philosophy each have important roles to play — one because of the power it now has and the other because of the power it ought to have — if we are to improve the moral climate in this country.
3. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Peter Gratton

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
With Eichmann in Jerusalem, we have, I would admit, a most unlikely case study for use in a business ethics classroom. The story of Eichmann is already some sixty years old, and his activities in his career as a Nazi were far beyond the pale of even the most egregious cases found in the typical business ethics case books. No doubt, there is some truth to the fact that introducing Eichmann’s story into an applied ethics class would inevitably depict an unseemly analogy between the practices of latter day corporations and the bureaucracy of the Nazi era. My argument here, though, is that the story of Adolf Eichmann, as depicted in Hannah Arendt’s well-known Eichmann in Jerusalem, offers a philosophically cogent account of judgment and ethical decision-making that future business managers and employees would do well to heed. Indeed, Eichmann in Jerusalem, originally a series of press accounts for New Yorker magazine, deserves consideration alongside the Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics, Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, and other classic ethics texts in a business ethics syllabus. This is not to say that Arendt’s work is uncontroversial; there are serious questions to be raised about both her depiction of Eichmann and her conclusions about “the banality of evil.” Nevertheless, her account of ethics, which, with its account of ethical duties and its case study of Eichmann’s character, shows both its Aristotelian and Kantian influences, is a warning to readers who would conflate morality with state laws and their duties with the needs of superiors. In short, I argue that, despite her well-known critique of modern large scale economies and her general avoidance of discussions of post-industrial corporations, Arendt may be a business ethicist of the first order.
4. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
James Hazelton

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
We consider whether public corporations can be ethical, using the notion of corporate social responsibility (CSR). We distinguish between ‘weak’ CSR (where corporate profitability is enhanced by pursuing social and environmental objectives) and ‘strong’ CSR (where it is not) and consider four possible positions in relation to strong CSR. First, CSR is unnecessary – good ethics is synonymous with good business. Second, CSR is unethical as the government is responsible for intervention in markets. Third, CSR is ethical and is being implemented by corporations. We find none of these positions convincing and argue a fourth position – CSR is ethical but impossible for corporations to implement due to competitive markets and the legal requirements of the corporate form. We conclude that public corporations are best considered amoral entities. In order to alleviate the inevitable negative social and environmental outcomes arising from corporate activities, we suggest strengthening the regulatory environment and using alternate organizational forms to conduct economic activities.
5. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
David R. Keller

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
H. E. May, J. S. Wigand

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Pursuant to the Doctrine of Consumer Sovereignty, we believe that tobacco companies should be compelled to disclose their ingredients so that the public health community can make more informed recommendations in order to protect consumer autonomy and sovereignty. However, a recent decision by the First Circuit precludes such a disclosure since it would be unduly burdensome to the industry, while granting only minimal gains to the public. We argue that many of the Court’s key claims rest on a misunderstanding of the science and chemistry of tobacco products. In our view, a mandatory disclosure of ingredients would more effectively protect the public interest, whilst posing minimal burdens on the tobacco industry.

book reviews

7. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Karim Dharamsi

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
John Scott Gray

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Brian Gregor

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Apple Zefelius Igrek

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Jon Mahoney

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
David B. Martens

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 2
Joseph Osei

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

editor’s introduction

14. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Peter H. Denton

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

essays

15. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Steven Benko

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As long as technology has been interpreted as an expression of practical reasoning and an effort to alter the conditions of human existence, ethical language has been used to interpret and critique technology’s meaning. When this happens technology is more than implements that are expressions of human intelligence and used towards practical ends in the natural world.1 As Frederick Ferre points out, technology is always about knowledge and values—what people want and what they want to avoid—and to the extent that technology increases power, one has to ask whether technology and/or the use towards which it is put is ethical.2 The ethicality of technology is based on whether that technology threatens or enhances the good for human beings. Therefore, any understanding of technology is never removed from ethics. Beyond the ethical evaluation of technology, technology is critiqued in light of whether it enhances or diminishes what it means to be human.
16. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Christine James

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
For a philosopher, the history of sonar technology is fascinating. During the first and second World Wars, sonar technology was primarily associated with activity on the part of the sonar technicians and researchers. Usually this activity is concerned with creation of sound waves under water, as in the classic “ping and echo”. The last fifteen years have seen a shift toward passive, ambient noise “acoustic daylight imaging” sonar. Along with this shift a new relationship has begun between sonar technicians and environmental ethics.
17. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Ana Cuevas

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, the different theories about science and technology relationships are analyzed. All of them have some virtues, but also one main defect: these theories do not take into account other well-founded possible relationships. The origin of this problem is the narrow view about science and technology. In this paper another characterization about technology based on Ronald Giere’s perspective is suggested. In the light of this new description, six different relationships between science and technology arise. Some of these relations had been explained in the before analyzed theories, but others emerge from the new portrayal.
18. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
James Farris

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Stefano Franchi

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Research in Artificial Intelligence has always had a very strong relationship with games and game-playing, and especially with chess. Workers in AI have always denied that this interest was more than purely accidental. Parlor games, they claimed, became a favorite topic of interest because they provided the ideal test case for any simulation of intelligence. Chess is the Drosophila of AI, it was said, with reference to the fruit-fly whose fast reproductive cycle made it into a favorite test bed for genetic theories for almost a century. In this paper I will try to show Artificial Intelligence’s relationship to games is quite different from what this analogy suggests. In fact, I will argue that AI is, at core, a theory of games and a theory of subjectivity as game-playing.
20. Essays in Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Ronald Godzinski Jr.

view |  rights & permissions | cited by