|
1.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Paul Lewis
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
2.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Jon Fennell
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
3.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
David W. Agler
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
4.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Alessio Tartaro
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
5.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Daniel Paksi,
Mihály Héder
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The two Hungarian authors of Guide to Personal Knowledge are in general agreement with the assessments of their work offered by David Alker and Alessio Tartaro. However, they contend that Jon Fennell’s criticism of their writing style, while sometimes accurate, nevertheless derives from an expected level of precision from non-native speakers of English that is unnecessary when the language is used as a lingua franca. Moreover, they suggest that underlying Fennell’s complaints about language are differences in the interpretation of Polanyi’s philosophy.
|
|
|
|
6.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Chris Mulherin
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
7.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Martin Turkis
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
8.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 2
Peter Blum
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
9.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Paul Lewis
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
10.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Michael Polanyi
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This is a recently discovered 1954 Polanyi lecture that was part of a lost eight-part series in Chicago. It develops Polanyi’s interest in unformalized personal participation in knowledge. The lecture discusses how normative “rules of rightness” work and Polanyi expands these ideas later in PK.
|
|
|
11.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Phil Mullins
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This short essay provides some historical notes helpful for understanding what Polanyi first called “rules of rightness” in his 1954 University of Chicago series of lecturess
|
|
|
12.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Walter Gulick
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Michael Polanyi’s essay “Rules of Rightness” argues that for living beings, both machine-like embodied processes and informal purposeful operations are guided by standards of proper functioning. This article traces the origins of rules of rightness back to the concomitant rise of life and purpose in the universe. Thereby the deterministic control of all things by the laws of physics and chemistry is broken. Powered by an independent active principle and guided by three inarticulate modes of learning, life takes on increasingly complex expressions of purpose in evolutionary history. Along the way, purposeful informal operations make use of and often create contrivances that further the explosive telic growth of life.
|
|
|
13.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Collin D. Barnes
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This brief commentary treats Polanyi’s newly found lecture, “Rules of Rightness,” as an occasion to revisit some earlier claims I made about the use of rating scales in social science research. It serves as something of an interim report on an ongoing inquiry into what an effective response to social science would look like from a Polanyian perspective.
|
|
|
14.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Andy Steiger
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Polanyi is widely known for his development of personal knowledge, but he was also keenly interested in what can be called, personal existence. The historical backdrop of reviving, the once dead language of, Egyptian Hieroglyphics provides valuable insights into Polanyi’s critique of objectivism and deciphering a human ontology. From applying physiognostic to telegnostic information to understanding static and dynamic meaning, Polanyi’s philosophy of language and machines provides a wealth of vantage points from which to study who and what we are.
|
|
|
|
15.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
C.P. Goodman,
Richard T. Allen
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
In this interview, C. P. Goodman invites British Polanyi scholar Richard T. Allen to reflect on his interest in Polanyi’s philosophical ideas and share what he believes is valuable in his thought.
|
|
|
|
16.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
49 >
Issue: 1
Phil Mullins
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
17.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
48 >
Issue: 3
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
18.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
48 >
Issue: 3
Paul Lewis
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
19.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
48 >
Issue: 3
Matthew Elmore
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article explores the common holdings of Thomas Aquinas and Michael Polanyi. More specifically, it suggests that Polanyi’s post-critical philosophy retrieves multiple aspects of the pre-Copernican rationality of Aquinas. First of all, both believe that the faculty of reason is never impartial; it is always committed, driven by the intellect’s appetite for satisfaction. Second, scientific knowledge requires habituation or know-how, which indicates that truth is not rational apart from bodily habitus. Third, reason operates only in a social body, and fourth, science can proceed only by faith in the authority of others. Along these lines, Polanyi relocates the modern scientist in something like a medieval body. Thus, some of Polanyi’s most important ideas are incidental recoveries of the paradigm Aquinas represents.
|
|
|
20.
|
Tradition and Discovery: The Polanyi Society Periodical:
Volume >
48 >
Issue: 3
Phil Mullins
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This historically oriented essay treats Michael Polanyi and Marjorie Grene’s discussions of Maurice Merleau-Ponty in their correspondence in the 1960s. It traces Grene’s growing enthusiasm for Merleau-Ponty and notes both Polanyi’s criticism and praise for Merleau-Ponty’s perspective in relation to his account of tacit knowing. The essay also comments on Polanyi’s criticism of Gilbert Ryle and his effort to align his perspective with Francis Walsh’s and F. S. Rothchild’s neurophysiological ideas about the operation of mind. I discuss the innovative Ford Foundation-funded conference program, spearheaded by Polanyi and Grene, that brought together an interdisciplinary group of scholars interested in transforming the prevailing philosophical paradigm. This project is the context in which discussion about Merleau-Ponty, Polanyi, and other figures flourished and Grene produced a complicated but fascinating set of little-known publications.
|
|
|