Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-14 of 14 documents


articles

1. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Dominik Balg

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I argue that there are significant instances of educational injustice in the context of philosophy teaching that can be effectively reduced by an increased implementation of digital technologies. More specifically, I show that there are good reasons to believe that testimonial injustices constitute serious instances of educational injustice that will frequently occur in philosophy classes. Using digital tools to anonymize student contributions opens up a promising way of dealing with these injustices. If convincing, my arguments give reason to perceive epistemic injustices in educational settings as a serious threat to educational justice and to reconsider the implications of increased digitalization for issues of educational justice.
2. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Dennis Earl

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Points-based grading, though now traditional, faces powerful critiques: Such grading creates a low road to passing, it undermines motivation, it wastes time, and it causes stress. It creates an illusion of mathematical precision. It is unfriendly to necessary conditions for satisfactory performance. This paper defends the alternative of specifications grading. Specifications grading grades only on whether work meets a set of expectations for satisfactory performance, with the expectations set at a high but reachable level. With a high bar also comes opportunities to revise unsatisfactory work. I summarize arguments from the literature in support of the system, but I also give account of my two-year experiment in philosophy courses with specifications grading. Compared with points-based grading, specifications grading appears to motivate students better and helps them learn more. I consider objections from both traditionalists and so-called ‘ungraders.’ The former hope to secure the benefits of specifications grading while still keeping points. The latter favor eliminating grading altogether.
3. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
William Goodwin

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper describes an approach to teaching the philosophy of science to science students that was developed in a context where the course is a lower-level requirement for all natural science majors. This audience made it appropriate to reconsider standard approaches to the field and resulted in an innovative pedagogical strategy subsequently used, in modified form, in more traditional philosophical contexts. This paper describes the pedagogical approach, explains reasons for it, motivates more specific ways of enacting it, and assess its value, not only for science students, but for philosophy majors as well.
4. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Theresa Helke

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this article, I present a philosophy-of-language assignment which emerges as the hero in a fable with the following trio of villains: Abstractness, Parroting, and Boredom. Building on Penny Weiss’s “Making History of Ideas Classes Relevant” (Teaching Philosophy 25[2] [June 2002]: 123–30; https://doi.org/10.5840/teachphil200225225), and serving students taking an introductory course which covers (at least) Western theories of meaning, the “You are there” essay conquers Abstractness by requiring students to make a connection between the material and their lives, rendering theories relevant. It conquers Parroting by requiring them to apply theories to new examples. And it conquers Boredom by producing papers whose originality can not only surprise but also remind the instructor reading them how meaningful the original theories are. In addition, I present a way to adapt the Weiss framework such that it’s (more) inclusive, and discuss my experience piloting and negotiating the assignment. As appendices, I include materials which an instructor can use to scaffold the assignment. Note that beyond dispatching Abstractness, Parroting, and Boredom, the assignment invites collaborative/cooperative learning, fosters learner autonomy, and lends itself to online course delivery.

book reviews

5. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Bryce Gessell

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Douglas Giles

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Jacquelyn Ann Kegley

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Steven Kelts

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
John Kinsey

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
George Matthews

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Neminemus

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Janelle Pötzsch

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Daniel Shaw

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 1
Patrick F. Walsh

view |  rights & permissions | cited by