|
1.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Billy Dunaway,
Jon McGinnis
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
2.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Joshua Kelleher
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
In this paper, I defend an unconventional mereological framework involving the doctrine of divine simplicity, to surmount a significant yet neglected dilemma resulting from that long-standing view of God as absolutely, and uniquely, simple. This framework establishes God as literally a part of everything—an “omni-part.” Although consequential for the many prominent religious traditions featuring divine simplicity, my analysis focuses on potential implications for an important formative issue in medieval Islamic philosophy. This problem of principality, with regards to metaphysical primacy and importance, derives from Ibn Sīnā’s celebrated distinction between essence and existence, and involves determining which is genuinely, objectively, real. Instead of supporting the historically dominant opposing viewpoints advancing either the principality of existence or of essence (aṣālat al-wujūd/al-māhiyya), I claim that God as omni-part aids renewed defence of the majority rejected view which upholds the combined principality of existence and essence together. Additionally, my proposal reinforces various theological desiderata including divine omnipresence and God’s necessity across possible worlds, while also supporting new perspectives on Ibn ‘Arabi’s influential notion of waḥdat al-wūjūd, understood as the absolute unity of being.
|
|
|
3.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Asha Lancaster-Thomas
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
In Abrahamic theism scripture is essential to belief-forming, yet scripture as an epistemic evidence source is plagued with difficulties. In the following article, I argue for a specific reductionist model of scriptural proposition justification utilising an account of scripture as testimony. I contend that for an individual to be justified in a belief sourced from a scriptural proposition, she must appeal to external evidence to “prop up her epistemic bar.” Accordingly, I consider some potential “epistemic bar-proppers.”
|
|
|
4.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Alireza Mazarian
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
What can we learn about the existence of non-physical entities (or a particular non-physical entity) from close inquiry into special kinds of experiences? Contemporary analytic philosophy has sometimes studied mystic experiences as evidence for the existence of such entities (for example, see: Broad 1939; Swinburne 2004; Plantinga 1981; Alston 1991). The article is organized as follows: first, I discuss several distinctions that seem to me to play substantive roles in philosophizing about such experiences. I will then offer and criticize two arguments that support the significance of the experiences. The arguments do not show whether a non-physical entity does or does not exist; they highlight a philosophical (and not theological) framework that can be beneficial to a variety of different approaches. Based on a heuristic strategy, the arguments will focus on the possibility/impossibility of objective representation of non-physical entities. They invite the reader (opponent, proponent, or neutral) to reflect on deeper philosophical grounds necessary for evaluating any positive or negative claims about the significance/insignificance of such experiences. The first argument rests on contemporary theories and assumptions. The second argument will use notions that drive from Classic Arabic-Persian Philosophy.
|
|
|
5.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Billy Dunaway
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Philosophers and theologians have traditionally been impressed with arguments which purport to show that predicates such as ‘wise,’ ‘good,’ and ‘powerful’ cannot, when applied to God, mean what they ordinarily mean when applied to everyday creatures. Theological predications, according to these arguments, cannot be univocal with ordinary predications. Philosophers in the Jewish, Christian, and Islamic traditions presented accounts of how non-univocal theological predications could be true of God. These are commonly known as analogical and apophatic accounts of the divine predicates. In this paper, I argue that representatives from each tradition also took epistemological constraints on an account of theological predication seriously. That is, they took it to be important to show not only how a predicate could be true of God, but also how we could know that it is true. Epistemological constraints of this kind, I argue, are non-trivial, since many accounts of the truth of theological predications entail that it is impossible or difficult to know them. Moreover, epistemological constraints are also important for ongoing discussions of theological predication, as they are violated by several contemporary accounts in the literature.
|
|
|
|
6.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Ian Olasov
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
7.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Yuiza T. Martínez-Rivera
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
8.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Beba Cibralic
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
9.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Michael Tofte
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
10.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Kathryn Mattingly Flynn
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
11.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
Jacob N. Caton
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
12.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
23 >
Issue: 1/2
James Murray
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
13.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Alex Sager
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
14.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Tiffany E. Montoya
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
While Spain was conquering new lands in the Americas, foreigners arrived into their own—the Gitanos. Spain imposed a double-standard whereby their crossing into new, occupied, territory was legitimate, but the entry of others into Spanish territory was not. I compare and contrast these historically parallel movements of people using Deleuze and Guattari’s taxonomy of movement (what they refer to as nomadology). I conclude that the double-standard of movement was due to differences of power between these two groups, understood in terms of material conditions, a prototypical “racial contract,” and differences in the relationship to land and space. This history and analysis of colonial Spain is a critical start for Latin American postcolonial theory; it gives us a framework to study philosophies of migration and nomadism; and finally, it introduces the Gitanos (and Roma in general) as an important population to complicate critical race theory or theories of ethnicity.
|
|
|
15.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Amy Reed-Sandoval
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
In this essay I explore how travel and border-crossing for abortion care constitutes a challenge to methodological nationalism, which serves to obscure such experiences from view. Drawing up field research conducted at two abortion clinics in Albuquerque, New Mexico, I also explore some implications of regarding pregnant people who travel for abortion care as a type of migrant, even (but not necessarily) if they are U.S. citizens and legal residents. Finally, I assess how this discursive shift can make important contributions to pandemic and migration ethics.
|
|
|
16.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Gajendran Ayyathurai
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Regardless of British colonial motives, many Indians migrated against caste/casteism across Indian, Atlantic, and Pacific Oceans. British Guiana marked the entry of Indian indentured laborers in the Caribbean in 1838. Paradoxically, thereafter religious and caste identities have risen among them. This article aims to unravel the intersectionality of religion, caste, and gender in the Caribbean Indian diaspora. Based on the recent field study in Guyana and Suriname as well as from the interdisciplinary sources, this essay examines: how brahminical deities, temples, and patriarchal institutions have re-invented caste-based asymmetrical sociality in the plantation colonies. Contrary to such re-establishment of brahminical inequalities, it argues, the castefree Indo-Guyanese religio-cultural practices foster inter-religious and inter-racial inclusive integration. And that this has led to self-transformation as well as in the making of a casteless society in the Caribbean.
|
|
|
17.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Michael Ball-Blakely
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Many supporters of open borders argue that restrictions on immigration are unjust in part because they undermine equal opportunity. Borders prevent the globally least-advantaged from pursuing desirable opportunities abroad, cementing arbitrary facts about birth and citizenship. In this paper I advance an argument from equal opportunity to global freedom of movement. In addition to preventing people from pursuing desirable opportunities, borders also create a prone, segregated population that can be dominated and exploited. Restrictions on mobility do not just trap people in bad opportunity sets—they help create bad opportunities by isolating the negative externalities of production and foreign policy. Freedom of movement can play a vital role in spreading risks and burdens, incentivizing their mitigation. Using an analysis of feudalism, segregation, and the transnational economy, I illustrate the centrality of space and mobility, showing why freedom of movement is a necessary tool for preventing political and economic oppression.
|
|
|
18.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Benjamin Boudou
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The concept of hospitality has seen a strong revival in the literature on migration and among pro-migrant activists. However, its meaning, its scope, and the nature of the obligations it imposes remain contested. Open-border advocates see hospitality as a moral principle of openness that should trump nationalist arguments for closure, while nationalists tap into the home analogy and compare the state to a household welcoming migrants as guests, whose stay should accordingly be temporary and marked by gratitude. Some consider hospitality a virtue that should translate into a personal responsibility to open one’s doors to others, while some politicise the concept to apply it to borders and state duties towards migrants. This paper unpacks the various literal and metaphorical meanings of the age-old concept of hospitality, and the shortcomings of its rhetorical uses. It then argues for a conception of hospitality as a principle of care towards displaced people. Hospitality alleviates ordinary obstacles that prevent a functional life in a new environment and allows for home-making practices. It is triggered by the vulnerability created by displacement, i.e., the material, emotional and political harms resulting from the loss of a home.
|
|
|
19.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Kyle Fruh
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
An increasingly wide array of moral arguments has coalesced in recent work on the question of how to confront the phenomenon of climate change driven displacement. Despite invoking a range of disparate moral principles, arguments addressing displacement across international borders seem to converge on a similar range of policy remedies: expansion of the 1951 Refugee Convention to include ecological refugees, expedited immigration (whether individual or collective), or, for entire political communities that have suffered displacement, even the ceding of sovereign territory. Curiously, this convergence is observable even across the distinction of interest for this paper: the distinction between arguments that proceed in the vein of reparations and arguments that reach their conclusion without invoking any reparations. Even though as a collection they appear to point in the same direction, I argue that non-reparative arguments that seek to address climate change driven displacement have several shortcomings, such that climate justice should be understood to include an indispensable role for reparations.
|
|
|
|
20.
|
Essays in Philosophy:
Volume >
22 >
Issue: 1/2
Codi Stevens
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|