|
1.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
James Barry
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
2.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
James Barry
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
3.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Jennifer Gaffney
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
4.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Tal Correm
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
5.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Robert P. Crease
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
6.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Benjamin P. Davis
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article examines how Hannah Arendt’s idea of a “right to have rights” could travel in the Americas. It offers a reading of the right to have rights that foregrounds the right to land as a basic right. This reading emerges through an attention to contemporary Indigenous social movements and political philosophy. Taken together, this examination and reading ask justice-oriented actors to support land back movements as part of a broader practice of defending human rights and situating those rights within a responsibility to land.
|
|
|
7.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Marilyn Nissim-Sabat
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
8.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Michael Weinman
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
9.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Hans Teerds
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This paper challenges the ideas beyond the application of smart technology in the urban environment by investigating the proposal for the waterfront of Toronto by Sidewalk Labs. Although the project has been cancelled in the first months of the COVID pandemic outbreak, it still offers a valuable case study, as it was developed by Sidewalk Labs, part of Alphabet Inc, the company behind, among others, Google. This paper focusses on the spatial, material, and political aspects of the proposal, which are investigated through an architectural reading of Hannah Arendt’s notion of the world. The paper reflects on the public spaces in the plan, and in particular to the ambition to make these spaces “responsive” to popular demand. This ideal is inherent to the most far-fledged convictions beyond smart cities. In contradiction to its promising images and wild ideas, this paper concludes that it silences the participants and diminishes the possibility of active participation in the built environment.
|
|
|
10.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Magnus Ferguson
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This paper situates Hannah Arendt’s concept of natality between the rival concerns of Habermasian critical theory and Gadamerian hermeneutical philosophy. I argue that natality is simultaneously emancipatory and hermeneutically grounded. This is to say that Arendt affirms the possibility of reflectively disrupting precedents set by tradition, even as she refrains from overestimating the emancipatory powers of critical reflection. Through comparison with Habermas and Gadamer, it emerges that Arendt conceives of repetition and revolution as jointly constitutive of human natality. At bottom, natality is not simply an innate capacity for newness, but rather refers to the site of an irreducible confrontation between past and future.
|
|
|
11.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Eduardo R. Cruz
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Transhumanism proposes human enhancement while regarding the human body as unfit for the future. This fulfills age-old aspirations for a perfect and durable body. We use “alienation” as a concept to analyze this mismatch between human aspirations and our current condition. For Hannah Arendt alienation may be accounted for in terms of earth- and world-alienation, as well as alienation from human nature, and especially from the given (“resentment of the given”). In transhumanism, the biological body is an impediment to human accomplishment. At most, this movement accepts “clean” bodies, not bodies with excretions. We argue that real human bodies are valued in the event of giving birth, so a modified concept that Arendt proposed, natality, seems a suitable way to explore the dialectic alienation-reconciliation involving the body (Arendt’s “A child has been born unto us”), when re-read by some feminist scholars.
|
|
|
12.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Meghan Robison
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This essay examines Arendt’s interpretation of Hobbes as it develops from “Expansion and the Philosophy of Power” (1946) and The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951) to The Human Condition (1958) by focusing on the role of the concept of process, and the reductive concept of life as “the life-process” in order to highlight an important way in which Arendt sees Hobbes as contributing to the valorization of the life-process in modernity. By reconstructing Arendt’s interpretation of Hobbes as it develops in these texts, I aim to expand our understanding of Hobbes’s importance for Arendt’s analysis of modernity by showing that Hobbes is not only the philosopher of an original “expansionist” concept of power and a political-economic imperialist state but also, on account of the centrality of the notion of process within it, key to the elevation of life as the highest value in the modern vita activa.
|
|
|
13.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Casper Verstegen
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Hannah Arendt’s concept of the mob has long been neglected. This paper aims to shine new light on the concept. It focusses on the mob’s role in Origins of Totalitarianism, as one of the key components in the rise of totalitarianism. First, this paper analyses Arendt’s definition of the mob. Next, it traces the mob’s origins, its growing influence, and two major ideological predispositions: tribal nationalism and rebellious nihilism. After further differentiation from Arendt’s concept of the masses, using the concept of the mob, the paper counters Robert Paxton’s objection to theories of atomized societies leading to fascism.
|
|
|
14.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Andrea Timár
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The paper suggests that Samuel Taylor Coleridge’s arguments against sympathy after the French Revolution, Walter Benjamin’s claims against empathy following the traumatic shock of Modernity and the First World War, and Hannah Arendt’s critical take on compassion. after the Holocaust are similar responses to singular historical crises. Reconsidering Arendt’s On Revolution (1963) and its evocation of Hermann Melville’s novella Billy Budd (1891), I show first that the novella bears the traces of an essay by Samuel Taylor Coleridge, “The Appeal to Law” (1809). Then, drawing on Walter Benjamin’s writings on trauma in Illuminations (1968, edited by Arendt), I discuss the political importance Arendt attaches to the proper way of telling a story, at a time when “the communicability of experience is decreasing” (Benjamin, Illuminations, 86). Through the analysis of Benjamin’s “The Storyteller” and Arendt’s “heartless” report on the Eichmann trial (1963), I equally show that, according to Arendt, testimonies must be narrated, or rather performed, in a dispassionate, dry, and compact manner so that they can be historically and politically relevant.
|
|
|
|
15.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Eric Ghosh
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
16.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Fanny Söderbäck
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
17.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
6
Jeanette Joy Harris
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
18.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
5
James Barry
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
|
19.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
5
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
20.
|
Arendt Studies:
Volume >
5
Lyndsey Stonebridge
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The failure of post-war institutions to fully grasp the depth and permanence of the placeless condition in the twentieth-century is at least in part responsible for the re-emergence of camps, barbed wire, sunken boats, and separated children in our own. As Seyla Benhabib demonstrates brilliantly, none of key intellectual exiles at the center of her book believed that political thought could simply accommodate the age of the refugee: the terms under which it operated had to shift with the moving world. I argue that there is an important kind of border poetics at work in these accounts of exile, migration and statelessness and within Benhabib’s analysis of the challenges that the placeless condition presents to the institutions of law and democracy today. This is no-coincidence. The modern history of placelessness required—and requires—a political imagination, and a language, that we are yet to fully appreciate or articulate. The wager of Benhabib’s book is how we might cultivate a poetics of exile which relinquishes claims to sweeping universalism whilst imagining the new forms we so urgently need to keep political life open to the differences and otherness that is its lifeblood.
|
|
|