Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-14 of 14 documents


news and notes

1. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

from the editor

2. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

features

3. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Philip Cafaro, Winthrop Staples III

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A serious commitment to environmentalism entails ending America’s population growth and hence a more restrictive immigration policy. The need to limit immigration necessarily follows when we combine a clear statement of our main environmental goals—living sustainably and sharing the landscape generously with nonhuman beings—with uncontroversial accounts of our current demographic trajectory and of the negative environmental effects of U.S. population growth, nationally and globally. Standard arguments for the immigration status quo or for an even more permissive immigration policy are without merit. Americans must choose between allowing continued high levels of immigration and creating a sustainable society.
4. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Robin Attfield

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
An interdisciplinary reappraisal of Lynn White, Jr.’s “The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis” reopens several issues, including the suggestion by Peter Harrison that White’s thesis was historical and that it is a mistake to regard it as theological. It also facilitates a comparison between “Roots” and White’s earlier book Medieval Technology and Social Change. In “Roots,” White discarded or de-emphasized numerous qualifications and nuances present in his earlier work so as to heighten the effect of certain rhetorical aphorisms and to generalize their scope and bearing well beyond what the evidence could bear. The meaning of Genesis and other biblical books proves to be just as important in White’s thesis as their historical reception. In “Roots,” White presents, alongside other contentions, the claims that Christian doctrines have all along been both anthropocentric and despotic, especially in the West, and that this is where the real roots of the problems are to be found. These claims, however, conflict with most of the relevant evidence. An adequate reappraisal of White’s work needs to recognize that there is a cultural determinism parallel to the technological determinisms alleged by R. H. Hilton and P. H. Sawyer, to endorse Elspeth Whitney’s “single-cause” critique of links between religion and technological change in the Middle Ages, and to treat sympathetically Whitney’s claim that White and some of his eco-theological critics (despite their disagreements) have in common both their valorizing of individual beliefs and values and their neglect of economic and institutional factors. Nevertheless, our ecological problems need to be understood through explanations turning on beliefs and values as well as on economics and institutions.

discussion papers

5. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Nicole Hassoun

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What should environmentalists say about free trade? Many environmentalists object to free trade by appealing the “Race to the Bottom Argument.” This argument is inconclusive, but there are reasons to worry about unrestricted free trade’s environmental effects nonetheless; the rules of trade embodied in institutions such as the World Trade Organization may be unjustifiable. Programs to compensate for trade-related environmental damage, appropriate trade barriers, and consumer movements may be necessary and desirable. At least environmentalists should consider these alternatives to unrestricted free trade if they do not prevent the achievement of other important moral objectives, can efficiently reduce environmental problems, and institutional safeguards can prevent their abuse.
6. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Nicole Klenk

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Analysis of academic forest scientists’ ethical reasoning and values given decision-making scenarios indicates that Holmes Rolston, III’s value theory, specifically his ethics of “following nature” is an important and current environmental ethics in forestry. Nevertheless, while academic forest scientists appear to espouse “following nature” in decision making, they also make use of numerous other values and ethics. Academic forest scientists’ moral reasoning is more akin to a pragmatic approach to decision making rather than an approach based on building or advocating an internally consistent and coherent moral position. Rolston’s environmental ethics is relevant and useful to decision making in forestry if it is interpreted as one among various value theories used to guide decision making rather than an ethical theory to be accepted or rejected en bloc.

book reviews

7. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
John Opie

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Frank W. Derringh

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Glenn Parsons

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Mick Smith

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Tom Spector

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Steve Vanderheiden

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Susan J. Armstrong

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

comment

14. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 31 > Issue: 1
Scott F. Aiken

view |  rights & permissions | cited by