Cover of The Leibniz Review
>> Go to Current Issue

The Leibniz Review

Volume 29, December 2019
Dedicated to Daniel Garber

Table of Contents

Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


1. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

articles

2. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
R. C. Sleigh, Jr.

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
3. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Robert Merrihew Adams

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
4. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Marleen Rozemond

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
5. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Paul Rateau

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

texts

6. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Wolfgang Lenzen

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Wolfgang Lenzen

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In the essay “Principia Calculi rationalis” Leibniz attempts to prove the theory of the syllogism within his own logic of concepts. This task would be quite easy if one made unrestricted use of the fundamental laws discovered by Leibniz, e.g., in the “General Inquiries” of 1686. In the essays of August 1690, Leibniz had developed some similar proofs which, however, he considered as unsatisfactory because they presupposed the unproven law of contraposition: “If concept A contains concept B, then conversely Non-B contains Non-A”. The proof in “Principia Calculi rationalis” appears to reach its goal without resorting to this law. However, it contains a subtle flaw which results from failing to postulate that the ingredient concepts have to be “possible”, i.e. self-consistent. Once this flaw is corrected, it turns out that the proof – though formally valid – would not have been approved by Leibniz because, again, it rests on an unproven principle even stronger than the law of contraposition.
8. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Lucia Oliveri

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews

9. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
François Duchesneau

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Dwight K. Lewis Jr.

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Christopher P. Noble

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Ohad Nachtomy

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Kristen Irwin

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Chloe Armstrong

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

translation, in memoriam, news, recent works, acknowledgements, abbreviation

16. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Antonio Lamarra, Catherine Fullarton, Ursula Goldenbaum

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The many equivocations that, in several respects, characterised the reception of Leibniz's Principes de la Nature et de la Grâce and Monadologie, up until the last century, find their origins in the genetic circumstances of their manuscripts, which gave rise to misinformation published in an anonymous review that appeared in the Leipzig Acta eruditorum in 1721. Archival research demonstrates that the author of this review, as well as of the Latin review of the Monadologie, which appeared, the same year, in the Supplementa of the Acta eruditorum, was Christian Wolff, who possessed a copy of the Leibnizian manuscrip since at least 1717. This translation figured as a precise cultural strategy that aimed to defuse any idealist interpretation of Leibniz’s monadology. An essential part of this strategy consists in reading the theory of pre-established harmony as a doctrine founded on a strictly dualistic substance metaphysics.
17. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29
Justin E. H. Smith

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. The Leibniz Review: Volume > 29

view |  rights & permissions | cited by