Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-11 of 11 documents


contents

1. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Ingrid Leman Stefanovic, Kenneth Maly

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

features

2. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Robert Frodeman

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The standard approach to environmental issues today is to turn to science, economics, or democratic populism as a means to resolve our environmental debates. Environmental philosophers, on the other hand, focus on the theoretical underpinnings of environmental issues, with possibly a brief reference to a specific case or example. A policy turn in environmental philosophy involves a third way, where philosophers begin from society’s own growing sense of the inadequacy of our conventional ways of addressing environmental problems.
3. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
David Seamon

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article examines the conception of the everyday city as presented in the work of architect Christopher Alexander and architectural theorist Bill Hillier. Both thinkers suggest that, in the past, lively urban places arose unself-consciously through the routine daily behaviors of many individual users coming together in supportive space and place. In different ways, both thinkers ask whether, today, a similar sort of vital urban district can be made to happen self-consciouslythrough explicit understanding transformed into design and policy principles. The aim for both Alexander and Hillier is place-based urban communities marked by lively streets, serendipitous public encounters, and informal sociability. The article begins by examining commonalities and differences in Alexander and Hillier’s conception of environmental wholeness and urban place. Next, the article considers implications for urban design and, finally, indicates the considerable value that the two thinkers’ ideas offer environmental philosophy, particularly for understanding environmental wholes.
4. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
W. S. K. Cameron

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Heidegger’s characterization of Dasein as Being-in-the-world suggests a natural relation to environmental philosophy. Among environmentalists, however, closer inspection must raise alarm, both since Heidegger’s approach is in some senses inescapably anthropocentric and since Dasein discovers its environment through its usability, serviceability, and accessibility. Yet Heidegger does not simply adopt a traditionally modern, instrumental view. The conditions under which the environment appears imply neither that the environment consists only of tools, nor that what is true of the parts is also true of the whole, nor that an orientation to use—where appropriate—precludes any other orientation. Heidegger’s anthropocentric commitments thus do not rule out the possibility of a non-instrumental perspective on the natural world.
5. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Bruce Foltz

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The beauty of nature has been neglected both in the history of aesthetics as well in environmental philosophy. Considering four philosophers of the last two centuries (Nietzsche and Heidegger in Germany, and Soloviev and Florensky in Russia) this paper outlines an understanding of the beauty of nature that is ontological rather than subjectivistic, and that terminates in a view of nature’s beauty as rooted in the phenomenon of the holy. This understanding, in turn, allows us to include certain important, but neglected issues within environmental philosophy, in addition to providing a unifying principle for environmentalphilosophy as a whole.
6. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Robert Chapman

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Wilderness and wildness are not related isomorphically. Wildness is the broader category; all instances of wilderness express wildness while all instances of wildness do not express wilderness. There is more than a logical distinction between wildness and wilderness, and what begins as an analytic distinction ends as an ontological one. A more rhetorical representation of this confusion is captured by the notion of synecdoche, where, in this case, wilderness the narrower term is used for wildness the more expansive term. Although this might seem obvious at first glance, I contend that the two concepts are often misused taken as synonyms thus equivocally, setting back the cause of conceptual clarity in environmental philosophy in general, and environmental restoration in particular. One notable outcome has been the unfortunate dichotomy between preservation and conservation resulting in policy choices that needlessly deny integrated alternatives by illicit exclusion. This paper will clarify this confusion by demonstrating instances where the two concepts have been systematically abused—conflated—and show how Henry David Thoreau saw them as importantly separable. Finally, a clearer understanding of the distinctions between the two concepts provides the basis for a viable program of restoration based on an ethics of place.

undergraduate perspectives

7. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Mary Edwards

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

discussion papers

8. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Kenneth Maly

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Bruce Martin

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book reviews

10. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
W. S. K. Cameron

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

report on books

11. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1

view |  rights & permissions | cited by