Cover of Philosophy Today
>> Go to Current Issue

Philosophy Today

Volume 65, Issue 2, Spring 2021
Philosophy after Automation

Table of Contents

Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


part i: interventions

1. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Yuk Hui Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
2. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jean-Luc Nancy, Daniel Ross Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Is “philosophy after automation” a theme or a question? One might hesitate about this, because we may wonder whether or not it implies that philosophy could disappear after automation, or at least be subject to serious revision. Philosophy could be read as a historical movement towards self-determination [autodétermination] as well as the exposition of the limit of such a program of archi-autonomy. The Cartesian event (a prominent moment of the automation mutation) is essentially ambivalent, and man alone in the world is undoubtedly also the one who can but alter, in the long run, the sufficiency of the auto. This is what we can now begin to understand.
3. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Bernard Stiegler, Daniel Ross Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Ours is an age of general automation. The factory that produced proletarians now extends to the biosphere; consequently, disautomatization is needed, which is the real meaning of autonomy. Autonomy and automatism must be reconceived as a composition rather than an opposition. Knowledge depends on hypomnesic automatisms that open up the possibility of what Socrates called “thinking for oneself”; digitalization thus requires a new epistemology that entails questions of political and libidinal economy. Today, automatization serves the autonomization of technics more than noetic autonomy, but reconceiving the latter necessarily involves reconsidering the meaning and character of desire. Greta Thunberg’s diagnosis of the irresponsibility of the generation before hers exposes the fact that the knowledge necessary to combat the consequences of contemporary technological development has been destroyed. The only possible counter to this irresponsibility lies in the reconstitution of knowledge, understood as the means by which humans struggle against entropy and anthropy.
4. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Michał Krzykawski Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article discusses translation as a technique of doing philosophy and introduces the concept of idiodiversity as an alternative to the current model of automated translation machines. The dominant functionalist approach to technology has made these machines the agents of linguistic homogenisation, which constitutes a threat for the diversity of idiomatic open systems this article advocates for. However, as this article argues, the challenge is not merely to accuse automated translation technologies of impoverishing the knowledge of how to translate but, rather, to determine whether these technologies can be reappropriated for the purpose of preservation and revalorisation of translation and, more generally, as a conveyor of noodiversity. This challenge also involves the need to draw attention to the political significance of translation practices and to elaborate an alternative to the mechanistic approaches to translation, typical of computational linguistics and language engineering, through a heterodox approach to cybernetics.
5. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Anna Longo

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In order to think of philosophy after automation, we have to ask if there is more in philosophy than the process of learning what philosophy is by inducing, from actual inferential practices, the future possible moves that are believed to produce philosophical truths. In the same way as the production of scientific hypothesis has been automated like a self-updating process which entails schemas of decisions and actions, philosophy itself, once conceived as a game where the truth of the statements is measured with respect to the social reproduction of inferential moves, could be automated as well.
6. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Babette Babich Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
To talk about automation and invisibility in our digitally projected world, I argue the case for the “cancelled” or lost voices of postphenomenology such as, most notably, Günther Anders. Reflecting on Nietzsche as on the role of GPS for location and for dating services like Grindr, I take up Nietzschean humanism (all-too humanism) including the fragility of his portable brass typing ball, latterly not unlike daisy wheel printer technologies and the programmed death of ink jet printers. With a casual reflection on pocket robots and screen-intentionality, GPS, triangulating perambulation, and programmed addiction, I raise the necropolitical question of climate change as of technology and its scotosis.
7. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Howard Caygill

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The article reflects on Heidegger’s admission in the 1966 Spiegel Interview that he was shocked by images of the Earth taken from space. It asks what these images were and shows that far from testifying to the encounter of planetary technics and the modern human they evince the meeting between an improvised automated technology of image capture and contingency.
8. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Yuk Hui

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article asks how can we articulate the limit of artificial intelligence, which virtually has no limit? Or maybe the definition of AI already implies its limit, how Marvin Minsky once declared that there is no generally accepted theory of intelligence, and that AI is only one particular way of modelling it. This article revisits the debate between Minsky and Hubert Dreyfus and repositions them in terms of an opposition between mechanism and organism, in order to expose the limit of Dreyfus’s Heideggerian critique. It suggests reflecting on the relation between noodiversity and technodiversity to methodologically broaden the concept of intelligence, and on how different concepts of intelligence could be thought by introducing the Chinese philosopher Mou Zongsan’s interpretation of Kant’s intellectual intuition.
9. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Katerina Kolozova Orcid-ID

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The scope of the paper is to present the concept of the radical dyad of the “non-human,” in an attempt to think radical humanity in terms of Marxian materialism, which is the product of approaching Marx’s writings on “the real” and “the physical” by way of François Laruelle’s non-philosophical method. Unlike posthumanism, inspired by critical theory and the method of poststructuralism, the theory of the non-human, as a radical dyad of technology in the generic sense of the word (ranging from the techné of speaking a natural language to AI technology) and the organic understood as physicality, does away with anthropocentrism. Moreover, it does away with any anthropomorphology of thought, that is, it does away with any theorizing or philosophy that is centered on the notion of (human) subjectivity or, to borrow a Laruellian term, any “posture of thought” that is molded according to the structure of subjectivity centered thinking,

part ii: dialogues

10. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Pieter Lemmens, Yuk Hui

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this dialogue with Yuk Hui, Pieter Lemmens explains the discipline called philosophy of technology and gives a concise overview of the most important contemporary approaches within this field. He also offers a critical evaluation of what are probably the two most salient characteristics of contemporary philosophy of technology, the so-called “empirical turn” and the “ethical turn,” which are deeply related and partly reflect the discipline’s on-going alignment with the global neoliberal agenda of exclusively profit-driven technological innovation. He also critically reflects on recent developments in the molecular and informational life sciences such as genomics, metabolomics, bioinformatics and synthetic biology.
11. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Eduardo Viveiros de Castro, Yuk Hui

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this dialogue with Yuk Hui, Eduardo Viveiros de Castro discusses his work on the Amerindian perspectivism, multinaturalism; the relation between nature, culture and technics in his ethnographic studies; as well as the necessity of a non-anthropocentric definition of technology. He also discusses a haunting futurism of ecological crisis and automation of the Anthropocene, and explores a “strategic primitivism” as survival tool.
12. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Hiroki Azuma, Yuk Hui

abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this dialogue, Hiroki Azuma discusses with Yuk Hui about the perception of technology in Japan after the defeat in the Second World War, from the Kyoto School to the postmodern critics, and the ambivalent conflicts between the modern and the tradition. The postmodern culture has a different signification in Japan than in the West as well as in other parts of Asia. Azuma documents the rise of the Otaku culture in Japan, and calls them “database animals,” a thesis that he formulated through his reading of Alexandre Kojève’s end of man and the absorption of the human subject into the technological world.

book reviews

13. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jonathan Basile Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jeffrey Epstein Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Miguel Gualdron Ramirez Orcid-ID

view |  rights & permissions | cited by

book discussion

16. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jessica S. Elkayam

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jennifer Gammage

view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Philosophy Today: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Mariana Ortega

view |  rights & permissions | cited by